Marcelo Dascal |
Ex pluribus unum?*
Patterns in 522+ Texts of Leibniz's
Sämtliche Schriften und Briefe
VI, 4
1. Introduction
2. Overview
2.1 At long last!
2.2 Material covered and thematic distribution
2.3 Indices, concordances, and some of what can
be learned from them
2.4 The problem of dating and the breakthrough
year
2.5 Leibniz's linguistic and publication policies
3. One picture
4. Another picture
5. Two pictures in
the same text
5.1 Recommendation
5.2 Purgatory
6. A three-pronged
breakthrough
6.1 General Inquiries
6.2 Discourse on Metaphysics
6.3 Examination of the Christian Religion
6.4 Inclining without necessitating
6.5 Human knowledge
6.6 Persuading without obligating
6.7 Division of labor
7. Impact
1. Introduction
“A major scholarly achievement”;
“The long awaited for result of painstaking and careful work, which surpasses
all expectations and justifies all the effort and funds invested in it”; “An indispensable tool for understanding
Leibniz’s thinking”; “A landmark in Leibniz research”; “A gift that contains
hitherto unpublished pearls and reveals hitherto unsuspected patterns in the
thinking of one of the greatest and most complex human minds”; “An
inexhaustible treasure whence generations of philosophers will draw profound
insights and wisdom”—these and many other superlatives have been competing in
my mind as I perused again and again the 3500++ pages of Volume 4 of Series VI
(henceforth VI.4) of the Academy Edition of Leibniz’s writings, the work I am
about to review here.
Needless to say, I
fully endorse every single one of the above superlatives: The more than a
decade long work of Heinrich Schepers and his collaborators in the Münster
Forschungstelle, whose outcome are these massive and dense four books into
which VI.4 is divided, certainly deserves all that praise and more. “Bravo!” I
would doubtlessly shout, were I present at a well-deserved concert-hall
premiere of a book that really turns out to be a masterful performance of a
polyphonically and structurally extremely rich creation of one of the greatest
masters in the history of human thought. (Here am I, again, adding superlatives
to my list.)
Short of further
rhetorical resources, I have to get down to business and squarely face the
extremely difficult and sui generis
task that this gigantic collection of texts of various types and degrees of
elaboration—texts stemming from different disciplines and domains, written for
different audiences, with different intentions and from different points of
view, and the vast majority of which were left unpublished by their
author—constitutes for a reviewer. For one cannot avoid the crucial question:
Which thread, which filum Ariadnes—as
Leibniz’s ubiquitous metaphor would put it—should one follow in sorting out,
selecting for special attention and discussion, and making sense of the mass of
concepts, theses, projects, arguments, comments on others’ work and discussion
thereof, and countless other details stored in this huge magazine of ideas the
volume under review in fact consists in—to borrow another Leibnizian metaphor?
The ideal thread, of
course, would be a master plan dictated by the intrinsic unity of the leibnizian system. But is there such
a thing? Is there a specifiable ultimate goal to which the particular goals of
each text or cluster of texts are subordinated, a systematic structure or
architecture, a set of fundamental methodological procedures uniformly applied
throughout all or most texts, a set of key concepts and/or principles, or any other
unifying factor that could indisputably be singled out in Leibniz’s mature
philosophical endeavors—which are those stored in the magazine before us? Can
one discern in these texts and reconstruct from their careful analysis a unity
in terms of which each would acquire its incontestable position, function and
meaning? Or perhaps there are several such plans, for each interpreter to pick
out at her choice? Perhaps what VI.4 reveals is this "Leibniz
pluriel" some interpreters talk about? Perhaps it shows, in spite of the
Editors' attempt to organize the mass of material it contains, an ultimately
unsystematic or pluri-systematic Leibniz, the plurality being irreducible to
any particular unity on pain of missing what it is all about?
Since these are
notoriously controversial interpretive questions, we should perhaps settle for
a more modest pragmatic thread, perhaps one hinted at by Leibniz himself, a
sort of inventory and road map he might had suggested for orienting the reader
in the miscellany of materials the book contains. Unfortunately, none of these
has been provided by Leibniz, who neither published himself nor collected these
writings chronologically and thematically as they are here presented. Perhaps
we should simply accept and follow the pragmatic thread fashioned by the
editors, clearly visible in the organization of the material and explicitly
explained and justified in Schepers’ Introduction. Or else, in case of
disagreement with them, the reviewer (as any other reader) should just follow
his or her own preferences, picking up for special comment those texts that
speak most to her or him, highlighting recurring themes and displaying whatever
significant connections between the texts s/he sees as showing their
coherence—i.e., following his or her own line of interpretation of the author’s
thought, either explicitly or implicitly. The reader of this review will
rightly suspect that this is what I will end up doing below—for what else could
I or anyone else do in what must be kept within the boundaries (which?) of an
unusual review such as the present one?
But I will try to do
something else too. I will also discuss both the implicit and explicit criteria
employed by the editors in their presentation and suggested interpretation of
the texts contained in VI.4. For I believe this is a way to try to shed some
light on central issues confronting any serious study of Leibniz’s complex
thought and his peculiar forms of writing and (not) publishing—a topic to which
the Introduction devotes much attention, and rightly so. Indeed, the
considerations underlying the organization of the book, along with the general
guidelines for its reading suggested in the Foreword and very substantial
Introduction, transcend their usual role of giving the reader some practical orientation.
In fact, they purport to be grounded on an intrinsic unity of purpose and
method the chief editor, undoubtedly one of the leading Leibniz scholars today,
discerns in the texts themselves—as he explicitly argues in the Introduction
and lets transpire in many of the short introductions to each particular text.
After an overview
exploring the volume's resources and already raising some critical questions
(Section 2), an attempt is made to identify the overarching pattern read into
the ensemble of the texts by the editors’ strong logically-oriented bias, which
is operative both in the selection of texts chosen for particular attention in
the Introduction and in their comments on these texts (Section 3). I then argue
that this bias leads to overlooking other important Leibnizian concerns and,
consequently, to hiding other patterns present in VI.4. In particular, I spell
out a cluster of motifs that form an alternative pattern, fundamental in my
opinion for understanding Leibniz’s rationalism and the nature of his
epistemology—a pattern that becomes visible once one looks at the material
through other glasses (Section 4). I try to show how the two patterns often
coexist in the same text through an analysis of some examples (Section 5). In
particular, I suggest a reading of the relationships between the major texts of
Leibniz's mature philosophy now critically edited in VI.4, which differs
from—perhaps complementing—the reading favored by the editors (Section 6). I
conclude by reconsidering from a broader perspective the issue of the impact
the publication of VI.4 is likely to have, both in advancing our understanding
of Leibniz’s ideas in the context of his time and—taking seriously the
programmatic and open-ended nature of many of his projects—in developing
Leibniz’s proposals in the context of our and future generations' philosophical
concerns (Section 7).
2. Overview
2.1 At long last!
In 1901 an inter-academic
committee decided to publish a complete critical edition of Leibniz's writings.
It was decided to sort out the writings in broad thematic categories and to
devote to each of them a "Series" comprising several volumes, as well
as a special Series containing his enormous correspondence. Each volume was to
contain, in chronological order, the writings or letters of a given period.
Soon it became apparent that the total mass of Leibniz's production—especially
the unpublished manuscripts, which form its vast majority—was far beyond what
had been anticipated. Furthermore, the difficulties in transcribing, comparing
different versions, and dating each manuscript were enormous, given Leibniz's
chronic lack of able secretaries and copyists and his habit of correcting
several times what he had written. In spite of continuous work by editorial
teams in three (now four) different locations in Germany, so far only 40 of the
(now) envisaged 120 large volumes averaging a thousand pages each have been
published. Some of the Series, such as the Political Writings and the
Correspondence advanced pretty well and are already reaching the last two
decades of Leibniz's life. Others—particularly the Philosophical Writings,
whose first volume was published only in 1971—remained somehow stuck in the
"young Leibniz" of the first decades, except for the extemporaneous
publication of the Nouveaux Essais by
A. Robinet (which will unfortunately require a second, thoroughly revised
edition).
The fourth volume of
the Philosophical Writings (VI.4), published in 1999, nearly a century after
the inter-academic decision, is the result of two full decades of work by the
Münster editorial team, under the direction of Heinrich Schepers.
Fortunately, Leibniz scholarship did not have to wait until 1999 in order to
begin to have access to the results of the work going on in Münster. A
pre-edition of ten yearly fascicles containing the already prepared texts was
circulated from 1982 to 1992 among Leibniz scholars, who could thereby also
modestly contribute to improving the final edition. But it is only by feeling
in one's arms the full weight of these four massive hard-bound volumes, rather
than the much lighter paperback ten fascicles, that one can appreciate the
amount of work invested and the magnitude of the result, and get a heavy
sensory clue to the 'weight' of its content. Perhaps in the future editions
such as these will be delivered only on computer disks, though I am afraid this
will never feel the same.
2.2 Material covered
and thematic distribution
Volume VI.4 contains 522 items
(some of them including several variants of the same writing), based on 612
manuscripts, spanning the period between the beginning of Leibniz's
employment by the House of Hanover as
ducal advisor and librarian (1677) and his long voyage to Southern Germany,
Austria and Italy (1687-1690). They are arranged in six thematic categories: A.
General Science, Characteristica, Universal Calculus; B. Metaphysics; C.
Natural Philosophy; D. Theology; E. Moral Philosophy; F. The Science of Natural
Law. Each part is, in its turn, subdivided in "Texts" and "Excerpts,
To Be Excerpted, Marginal Notes". The selection criterion for inclusion of
an item in this volume, reflected in its thematic organization, is based on
what is described as a "a broader conception of philosophy" (p. xi),
which encompasses also writings on the foundations of natural law (F) [with the
exclusion of the lengthy and important comments on Lauterbach's Compendium Juris (1679) which is left
for a Supplementary Volume], on theology (D) [with the exclusion of those
writings "oriented towards theological controversies" (ibid.)], and
"elementary writings" on natural philosophy (C) [the more technical
ones being left to the newly created Series VIII which is to contain the
Scientific and Technical Writings]. One misses similar extensions of the
collection at least regarding the "elementary" mathematical writings
and at least the non-polemical political ones—both of philosophical
significance. The importance the editors correctly attach to Leibniz's
reactions to his readings in the period covered is reflected in the fact that
roughly one third of the volume's contents is represented by the "Excerpts
and Marginal Notes" subdivisions.
In
terms of the amount of individual texts (247) and number of pages (1345),
category A is by far the largest, followed by B (104 texts, 610 pages), D (68
texts, 578 pages), F (36 texts, 198 pages), C (33 texts, 162 pages), and E (34
texts, 46 pages). Leaving aside the Moral Philosophy category, which is
surprisingly small and contains many virtually undated short texts, it is worth
noticing that, by comparison with their total number of pages, the Metaphysics
and Theology categories are those with the largest proportion of pages in their
Excerpts and Marginalia subdivisions (more than 40% each), whereas the Scientia Generalis, Natural Philosophy
and Law categories have each only slightly over 20% of excerpts and marginalia.
What exactly these proportions indicate is hard to figure out. On the one hand
they reflect the fact that in metaphysics and in theology Leibniz devoted much
time to the critical study of authors whose views he either followed or
antagonized—a phenomenon characteristic of his thought. This phenomenon is also
non-negligible, though less frequent in the Scientia
Generalis category, perhaps because he considered his contributions in this
domain as less controversial than, say, in metaphysics.
A question that
requires further elucidation is whether the impressive fact that the Scientia Generalis field covers 46% of
the material in VI.4 may be indeed taken as a sure indication that it constitutes
the core of Leibniz's philosophical
work and interests between 1677 and 1690 and irradiates its influence over all
the other fields—as the editors seem to take for granted. This impression might
rather be the residual result of the original division of the Academy Edition
into thematic Series, whose arbitrariness the editors admit (p. lxxxiv) and
seek to remedy by broadening the criteria for determining philosophically
relevant material—which is of course most welcome. Yet, besides the further
extensions I suggested above, I must add that I am not happy with their giving
up a separate Epistemology category in the volume's thematic organization.
Instead, they included texts that clearly belong to what was traditionally
known as the "theory of knowledge" in the Scientia Generalis category. To be sure, the questions of method,
of conceptual and linguistic analysis, and of the formal development of
special-purpose calculi as well as of a universal calculus, which form the bulk
of category A, are closely connected with the epistemological questions about
the nature of ideas and their representation, of cognition and of what is
cognizable, and of truth. Nevertheless, the latter have been traditionally as
well as by Leibniz himself viewed as a distinctive cluster of issues, not
necessarily subordinated to the formal approach typical of the former. The fact
that one of the rare texts Leibniz published in this period is the well-known Meditationes de Cognitione, Veritate et
Ideis (1684), which deals with this epistemological cluster of issues,
indicates how important Leibniz considered this domain to be, and would per se
justify selecting similar texts as its companions for a separate category. In
fact, the list of about twenty texts mentioned on page lviii in connection with
the Meditationes would have been a
good starting point for this purpose.
2.3 Indices,
concordances, and some of what can be learned from them
The editors showed great care in
providing 500 pages of indices and concordances of various types (subjects,
names, writings referred to, quotations from the Old and New Testament, etc.)
and binding these pages handily in a separate sub-volume. Leibniz would be pleased
to see that his often repeated recommendation to endow his projected
encyclopedia with as many indices as possible was judiciously followed by his
literary executors and applied to his own encyclopedic work. These indices and
concordances, as well as the Introduction, the Table of Contents, and the
editorial introductions to each text, provide valuable systematic information
that can be translated into guidelines for the reader interested in where to
begin his/her reading, as well as for the researcher interested in discovering
hitherto unnoticed aspects of Leibniz's thought. In fact one can draw from
these sources a sort of synopsis of the materials contained in the volume—in
the spirit of Leibniz who considered synoptic tables to be excellent mnemonic
and discovery tools. Here are some examples of what could be learned through a
statistical-synoptic exercise of this kind.
From the name,
writings, and subject indices, in addition to finding a particular reference or
use of a concept, one may gather such important information as who are the
authors and writings most often mentioned by Leibniz, what are the concepts
most often used by him, etc. One may be in for some surprises. For example,
Descartes is by far the most mentioned 17th century author, but the
next in line is the
From the concordances
linking the pre-edition and the published volume one learns that 26 texts of
the pre-edition are not included in the volume, while 9 new ones have been
added. The main reason for this is more accurate dating.
Another concordance
shows the amount of material here published that was already available in the
main earlier editions: Couturat (118 texts), Grua (96), and Gerhardt (48). If
we take into account that some of the here published texts were published in
previous editions other than these three, that there is some overlapping
between these editions (especially between Gerhardt and the other two), and
that many of the previously published texts were published only partially and
appear here for the first time in complete version, it turns out that VI.4
contains an impressive amount of texts published for the first time—slightly
more than the 222 mentioned in the Foreword (p. xli).
2.4 The problem of
dating and the breakthrough year
From the Table of Contents we can
single out the largest texts, the smaller texts in multiple variants (which
indicates how much attention Leibniz devoted to their elaboration), and the
one-shot pieces. The introduction to each text explains the grounds for its
presumed date. This is no easy or uncontroversial matter, for Leibniz dated
only 38 texts (a list of the dated texts would have been helpful). For dating
the others, the editors rely on an "external" (paper watermarks) and
on an "internal" (thematic and terminological similarity) criterion,
neither of which is precise and decisive, thus leaving sometimes an excessively
large time interval of several years as the presumed date. Consequently, there
is no hope of meeting the ideal of knowing what Leibniz thought/wrote each day,
not even with the help of the correspondence. Nevertheless it would be possible
to have a chronological concordance (not provided) approaching the ideal in
question. This would be particularly useful for those interested in (a)
establishing the "correspondence" between apparently unrelated texts
written more or less at the same time and (b) suggesting some kind of
diachronic evolution in Leibniz's thought.
A more precise dating
is of particular interest in view of the fact that the mid-eighties are the
years in the course of which the mature thought of Leibniz in several domains
crystallizes in the form of thoroughly elaborated relatively large texts,
easily identified through the Table of Contents and the headings, apparently
'surrounded' by smaller pieces related to them perhaps as preparatory sketches,
auxiliary material, etc. It would be very useful to know the temporal sequence
in which all this material was written. The major texts referred to include the
justly notorious Discours de Metaphysique,
the Generales Inquisitiones, and the Examen Religionis Christianae (also
known as "Theological System"). Fortunately, the (broad) dating of
these major texts is relatively uncontroversial: in all likelihood they were
all written in the crucial year of 1686. Along with the smaller pieces directly
related to them and well elaborated texts in neighboring domains (e.g., the Meditationes published by Leibniz and
written in the second half of 1684), we can speak of a span of a couple of
years of intense philosophical work, in which a cluster of extremely
significant texts for the understanding of Leibniz's mature philosophy is
produced. Just as Leibniz noted, next to the title of the logical treatise Generales Inquisitiones, "here I
have made excellent progress", he could have said the same of its
coetaneous counterparts in metaphysics, theology, linguistics, epistemology,
and other fields as well. The mandatory question is whether and how the
advances he himself was aware of having made in all these fields are correlated—a
question to be explored below. The answer, whatever it is, should have fundamental
implications for assessing the nature of Leibniz's "system".
2.5
Leibniz's linguistic and publication
policies
Another point that emerges
clearly from the statistics of VI.4 is Leibniz's peculiar linguistic and
publication policies. Concerning the latter, as noted, he published only three
pieces out of the whole material here contained. Concerning the former, the
data are also overwhelming: very few texts are in German, 12% are in French,
and the rest in Latin. If one were to take Russell's dictum that only Leibniz's
Latin writings represented his philosophically and scientifically serious
views, this would mean that in this period of his life he had very serious
things to say, as compared with the later periods, in which he wrote two major
books (the Nouveaux Essais and the Théodicée) in French. Pace Russell, however, the fact is that
both his publication and choice of language decisions were basically guided by
audience- and circumstance-oriented criteria. VI.4 contains, for example, two
translations made by Leibniz. In 1685 he translated from German into French a
dialogue between a devout person and a confessor that constituted the Preface
of the Jesuit Friedrich von Spee's Golden
Book of Virtues (1649). This he later (1697) corrected and made available
to the Duchess Sophie, with whom he usually corresponded in French. Already in
1677 he had praised Spee's book not only for its "solid piety" but
also for its inspiring rhetorical virtues, which makes it fit "to be in
the hands of all Christians", Protestant and Catholics alike (p. 2515).
"This is the true mystery of secret theology, which I don't know”—says
Leibniz—“whether anyone (surely in
Leibniz's astonishing
"non-publishing" record is a more complex issue. Different
explanations of this policy for some of the leibnizian writings and projects
are considered in the Introduction in some detail. The need for secrecy in
order to avoid self-defeating effects is the most often invoked reason. Thus,
on the assumption that the mega-project of a Scientia Generalis—which Schepers in the Introduction considers the
basis for understanding most of Leibniz's work in this period—is deliberately
kept secret by Leibniz, the chief editor explains this decision in terms of the
enormous scope of the project, which involved both scientific and practical or
political dangers. On the one hand, it would be difficult, he argues (pp. lii,
lvii), to find the necessary scientific collaborators if they knew that their
work, say, in a new encyclopedia or in compiling definitions, was nothing but a
component of the larger aim of providing material for an "art of
discovery" and for the analysis of concepts that was to lead to the Characteristica Universalis. They would
hardly understand these ulterior aims and might be discouraged by their
excessively ambitious scope. (On page lxxxv, a similar attitude is ascribed to
Leibniz vis-à-vis the host of collaborators needed for his project of
law reform.) On the practical, personal and political level, according to
Schepers, Leibniz rejected employment offers (in the university, in the French
Academy, in the Vatican library) because he didn't consider these to be
appropriate venues for carrying out his mega-project, and accepted the Hanover
offer because of its prospects in this respect; he later realized that
Hanover's resources were not sufficient and sought support in wealthier and
more powerful spheres—the Emperor, the Pope, Louis XIV. Yet, Schepers himself
asks (p. lxxxv): what prince or king would in his sane mind espouse and finance
a project whose ultimate aim is "the happiness of humankind"? In
fact, would any ruler (unfortunately, not only at the time) be able to
understand the significance of the project and see in its achievement a mission
consonant with his ultimate duties and interests? All indicates that, in spite
of his secret contacts and efforts, Leibniz's project was condemned to waiting
for the opportunity, the kairós, that never came (p. lxxxvi).
Ultimately, he had not only to keep the project secret, but actually to bury
it, contenting himself with producing instances (specimina) and general principles (initia) he considered as no more than mere illustrations—themselves
kept unpublished—of what the Scientia Generalis
might have been had it received the support it deserved.
A similar fate was
reserved for his major metaphysical and theological works, for similar
reasons—according to the Introduction. The Discours
de Metaphysique was not kept in Leibniz's drawers because of the
unfavorable reaction of Arnauld, a distinguished and most capable
representative of the learned world that Leibniz 'used' as a test ground for
his revolutionary metaphysics. The reason, according to the Introduction, was
rather its complexity and sophistication (pp. lxx-lxxi). Derived from a few
incontestable principles, Leibniz's metaphysics required an "inexorably
rational" effort for grasping its radical consequences without falling
prey to apparent inconsistencies. Viewed as a whole, it is hyper-complex and
requires the sophistication of a mathematical mind—a tinctura matheseos (p. lxxi) alien even to "the Great
Arnauld"—for its proper understanding. Its improper understanding, on the
other hand, might easily lead (as it in fact did) to accusations of
"spinozism" and other politically pregnant allegations of atheism. As
for the Examen religionis Christianae,
praised in the Introduction for its rigorous demonstrative structure, it was
primarily conceived to provide the systematic ground—expressing Leibniz's basic
beliefs and principles but also palatable to Rome—for the reunification of
Christian confessions. Unless there were previous assurances that the Catholic
Church would "tolerate" it for this purpose, there was no point in
publishing it. In spite of Leibniz's careful steps to obtain such assurances at
least from "moderate" Catholic bishops (pp. lxxvi, lxxviii), he did
not obtain them: once more the circumstances prevented the publication of this
virtually complete and masterful text (p. lxxx). The four complete dialogues
that Baruzi called 'mystical', especially the long and beautiful anti-skeptical
Conversation du Marquis de Pianese et du
Père Emery Eremite, in their turn, are said not to have been
published due to Leibniz's fear of raising the suspicion of heresy (p. lxxx).
No doubt there is
some basis for the restraints in publishing attributed to Leibniz in the above
explanations. They correctly highlight the fact that Leibniz was no 'pure'
intellectual, but rather a 'political animal' (cf. p. xlviii) in the good sense
of the term, for—in the footsteps of Bacon—he considered knowledge, first and
foremost, as a tool for the improvement of humankind. They also indicate his
awareness of the innovative, sometimes revolutionary, nature of his ideas and,
consequently, his doubts about the capacity of his contemporaries to understand
them. Nevertheless the explanations adduced are far from compelling, to say the
least—and not only because they also present a man of Leibniz's stature as
excessively concerned with his reputation (pp. lxxxiii, lxxxv) and
exaggeratedly fearful of the personal and public consequences of revealing the
truths he was sure to have discovered. Maybe this is true and character was not
one of his strengths, although his concerns were no doubt justified: Who would
dispute the need for first building a solid reputation for oneself in order to be
able to advance one's more ambitious projects (p. xlix) and, in general,
"the necessity of a good name and respect" (as he titled one of his
little practical morality pieces—A IV 3, pp. 883-887)? Wouldn't it be foolish
to overlook the danger of being considered a "chimerical philosopher"
if he were to publish his metaphysics (p. lxxi), in the light of Arnauld's
allegation that Malebranche's metaphysics was that of a visionnaire—a fear later confirmed when Bayle described Leibniz's
own metaphysics as bizarre? Could one
forget the grim lesson of Galileo's trial, ever present in Leibniz's mind (p.
2068; p. lxxvi; see also VI.1, p. 265)?.
Still, the
explanations offered are, in most cases, not the only possible ones, so that at
best they form only part of the cluster of reasons that inclined him not to
publish. In the Scientia Generalis
case, for example, it might simply be the case that he realized how utopian the
mega-project was and settled for whatever specimina
and initia he could actually
deliver—none of which he considered fit for publication. We should not forget
too that he did write quite a few "prefaces" which are in fact something
like advertisement tracts depicting the marvels of the mega-project or of some
part thereof, which were intended for scholars as well as for possible
financial and political supporters. In this way he made his project public,
albeit without formally publishing it. Furthermore, in his later, widely
distributed memoirs on 'scientific policy', dealing with the creation of academies
and scientific societies, he referred to his ideal of a general science and its
aims. Similarly, not too long after the Discours
de Metaphysique, he published in the Journal
des Sçavants (1695) the "New System of the Nature and the
Communication of Substances, as well as the
3. One picture
It is quite clear that the
editors of VI.4—especially the chief editor—see the chronological cross-section
of Leibniz's philosophical work collected in this volume in terms of a
predominant picture that endows the whole collection with whatever coherence a
collection of this kind may reasonably be expected to have.
Unlike previous
editions, which were not subject to the constraints of comprehensiveness of the
Academy Edition, and therefore were openly selective in their choice of texts,
the present edition can be safely assumed to be objective in this respect.
Therefore, we can further assume that the systematic pattern or picture the
editors discern mainly emerges so to speak "bottom up", i.e., out of
their deep familiarity with the texts of VI.4, although one cannot altogether
discard the possibility that they have been subject also to the "top
down" influence of one or another entrenched conception about "what
really matters" for a rationalist like Leibniz.
The image of Leibniz
the Introduction espouses from the outset is that of a man animated by a global
philosophical project, which requires a "revolutionary work that will
ground knowledge—the basis of our rational interaction—upon a new, more secure
foundation" (p. xlviii). On this view Leibniz perceived himself as a
'radical rationalist' who, "in all fields of spiritual activity, saw his
strength in the radical, i.e., directed to the first roots, use of reason"
(p. xlvii).
Not surprisingly, the
term 'reason' (Vernunft) is one of
the most used in the Introduction—as it is in the texts themselves, as revealed
by the Subject Index. To the editors'
merit, however, it should be noted that they insist in the fact that this
particular rationalist also happened to be deeply concerned with the common
good, with justice and with faith, for he was a sincere believer—a fact often
forgotten by other interpreters. So that what mattered most for him was to use
reason for the improvement of the human condition and to combine or reconcile
reason with faith. Still, in the picture they present it is reason rather than
his other values that has the upper hand, the latter having to be accommodated
in terms of the parameters of the former. Of course, this might be nothing but
the effect of the objective fact that 40% of VI.4's texts presumably deal with
matters of reason alone, with faith and other leibnizian concerns remaining at
best in the background.
What are the
parameters of this "radical reason" singled out in the editors'
picture? Briefly put, they are essentially logic-related: The analysis of
concepts into a few primitive ones yielding precise definitions reflecting
conceptual structure; the use of demonstration conceived as a chain of
substitutions based on such definitions until one reaches an identity
proposition; the formalization of the above through an appropriate notation and
a universal calculus specifying all valid inferences, which would ensure a
foolproof decision procedure for determining truth and resolving controversies
as easily as in arithmetic; the use of the mathematical "art of
combinations" as the backbone of the method of discovery; and above all
the systematization of all knowledge in a quasi-axiomatic structure leading
from the simple to the complex, from the foundations to their ultimate
rigorously derived consequences. Along with the project of a new,
demonstratively ordered encyclopedia that would be a central tool for the
"art of discovery" (for it would make patent the pieces of knowledge
still missing as well as those still lacking an appropriate foundation), these
parameters are those that characterize the mega-project of a Scientia Generalis—an expression Leibniz
began to use in his first years in Hanover.
According to the
Introduction, it is this predominantly logical notion of
"reason"—where analyze!, demonstrate!, formalize!, calculate!, and
axiomatize! are the key injunctions—that underlies and informs the bulk of
Leibniz's intellectual activities in the period covered by VI.4. Accordingly,
it highlights the presence of these motifs in virtually every single text it
comments upon, while downplaying or not noticing at all the elements that do
not fit the favored picture. By pointing this out, I am not suggesting that the
Introduction's comments on these texts are either "wrong" or useless,
but rather that they tend to overlook significant aspects of these texts—aspects
which, were they noticed, could lead to an alternative picture.
4. Another picture
The alternative picture I am
going to suggest has also emerged "bottom up". Reading, re-reading,
teaching, and discussing the texts of the pre-edition in my seminars and
research groups, I had the feeling something was missing in the usual way of
viewing them, forcefully spelled out in the 'radical reason' picture. I didn't
know what it was, but it seemed to me important enough to keep trying to find
out. It was not easy because, as so many researchers, in my previous work on
Leibniz I had been working under the spell of this picture, which seemed so
natural, so persuasive, so logical. Now I am perhaps under the no weaker spell
of the other picture, which leads me, I admit, to detect its traces in
virtually every text. Fortunately, the Gestalt shift is not so absolute that,
having seen the face, one cannot go back and see the rabbit.
In any case, perhaps
under the pressure of too many unexplained things I had to brush under the
carpet, another pattern took shape in my mind. It stems from the attempt to
re-evaluate the non-negligible amount of texts or parts of texts that are
either ignored by the 'radical reason' model or, when noticed, are accommodated
by this model only very uncomfortably and partially, thus failing to do justice
to what is perhaps hidden in them. The image that comes to my mind is that of a
vision that focuses on the easily visible full half of a glass, discarding
whatever spots there are in the 'empty' half as worthless dirt or 'noise'. What
the alternative vision reveals is that the other half is not empty at all, that
the dirt is in fact valuable ore worth mining.
This ore contains, among many other valuables, the
acknowledgment of the essential role of and consequent need to investigate and
develop the theory and applications of: presumptions that rationally justify
conclusions without actually proving them in a formal sense; a hermeneutics
capable of taking account of the specific contextual characteristics in which a
text is produced or applied in order to determine its appropriate
interpretation; an ethics of communication whose basic principle is a principle
of charity that presumes the reasonableness and truth of the interlocutor's or
author's utterance or text, an attitude that requires the hearer or interpreter
to make all the effort needed in order to understand properly "the other",
prior to critique or dismissal; a rhetoric of persuasion whose efficacy is
predicated upon the use of situated argumentation, which argues from premises
acceptable to the audience and takes into account both the relevant context and
co-text; non-quantifiable methods for evaluating reasons pro and con a
decision; a 'heuristics' (including, among other things, parts of the Topics and the Rhetoric) as a fundamental component of the "art of
discovery", which in principle forms at least half of the General Science
project; analogical arguments, whose cognitive import is undeniable and yet
have no non-analogical counterparts; systematic structure viewed in terms of
horizontal analogical relations rather than vertical, i.e. hierarchic
deductive/linear relations; epistemic means that can face the skeptical
challenge without relying upon the problematic search of absolute certainty;
conflict-resolution negotiations run in the spirit of minimalist rather than
maximalist strategies, designed for consensus-building and mutual toleration
rather than opposition-enhancing; the actual use of all of these or part
thereof in the most diverse domains such as jurisprudence, medicine, theology,
politics, science, ethics, epistemology, and in the Scientia Generalis itself.
These phenomena are
present, at the practical as well as the theoretical levels, in the texts
collected in VI.4. In the following sections I discuss in detail a number of
texts, analyzing their relationship with the two pictures. Here, very briefly,
I mention a few other examples, belonging to different thematic categories,
where the phenomena that configure the second picture can be clearly discerned.
The Conversation du Marquis de Pianese et
du Père Emery Eremite (pp.
2240-2283), included in the theological category of VI.4, is an
epistemologically important dialogue that beautifully illustrates, step after
step, the argumentative strategy of arguing from premises accepted by the
interlocutor (who
presents himself as a skeptic) in order to overcome skepticism. The De Deo trino (pp. 2291-2294) provides a
'proof' of the trinity based on an analogy with the human mind, which can be
favorably compared with the analytic treatment of the same topic in the more or
less coetaneous De trinitate (p.
2346). In Spongia exprobationum
("A shield against censorship: that no kind of true doctrine should be
despised", pp. 729-735), whose value the Introduction sees in its defense
of 'interdisciplinarity' (p. lvi), Leibniz in fact argues against the
"method of exclusion", on the grounds that every serious doctrine or
method, if attentively and charitably examined, contains weaknesses as well as
strengths, so that no one can erect itself as the arbiter of all the others—a
true eclectic manifesto. Finally, in La
place d'autruy ("The place of the other"), which the Introduction
(p. lxxii) would have included in the Ethics division had it not been already
published (IV.3, pp. 903-904), Leibniz presents the Christian charity principle
of taking into account the point of view of the other as much as possible as a
fundamental guideline for both ethical and strategic action. Other texts
highlighting the second picture can be found in the forthcoming collection of
texts G. W. Leibniz: The Art of
Controversies and Other Writings in Logic and Dialectics (M. Dascal and Q.
Racionero, eds.).
There is, thus, a
whole set of phenomena, dealt with in a significant number of texts, which
transcend the radical reason picture because, on the face of it, they do not
conform to—and perhaps cannot be handled in terms of—its basic injunctions,
which call for complete analysis, definition, demonstration, and a special form
of systematization. No doubt the procedures underlying these phenomena are
systematic in their way, which bears, however, little resemblance to the more geometrico model or any other
version of the logical-mathematical ideal favored in the radical reason
picture. For, they respond to needs that are best handled in other, 'softer'
ways exemplified by the list above, ways that do not privilege the quest for
order and certainty above all the rest. By bringing together phenomena such as
the ones listed above, a pattern of Leibniz's concern with a kind of 'soft
rationality' the radical reason picture does not acknowledge clearly emerges.
Defenders of the
radical reason picture might argue that there is nothing in the phenomena
mentioned that could not be, in principle, handled by the methods
characteristic of the radical reason model. Consider a few possible examples of
this objection. Probabilistic inferences—the objection would run—are, to be
sure, 'weaker' in the sense that their conclusions have a probability tag
attached to them, but as Leibniz himself has shown in his essays on the
calculus of probabilities (e.g., in "The evaluation of the uncertain",
pp. 92-101), "one can always give demonstrations regarding the probability
itself" (p. 707). Legal interpretation and the justification of laws can
be systematically handled in terms of precise criteria based on analytic
definitions, so as to minimize—if not altogether eliminate—the reliance on
dubious hermeneutic and justificatory practices. Even the structure of debates
can be formally represented so as to ensure that no contribution to the debate
is omitted, thus yielding a "Method of disputing until the exhaustion of
an issue"—as the title of a little piece advertises (pp. 576-578).
To these objections
one might reply, respectively: (A) The so-called calculus of probabilities in
fact provides rules for deducing the probability of a compound outcome given the probabilities of its
components, and in this it is perfectly deductive; what 'weakens' this calculus
are rather the problems that arise in the quantification of the components'
probabilities and their respective weight in the compound outcome; whereas these
problems can be solved without principled difficulties in those cases—such as
card games or dice (dealt with in "The evaluation of the
uncertain")—where the formal structure of the game's constitutive rules in
fact determines the analysis, this is not the case in general. (B) A text like
the "The interpretation, grounds, and system of laws" (pp.
2782-2791), which the Introduction (p. lxxxiv) considers as a juridical example
of the radical reason model, undoubtedly has an analytic and demonstrative
flavor; yet, the flavor in this case remains flavor and the pudding is quite
another story; for this rigorous text, after saying that interpretation
involves both interpreting "what is said" and "what is
thought" (by the legislator), and providing approximate guidelines for
handling the former question, defines the latter as "the search for what
the legislator … had in mind regarding the issue at hand, that is what he would
have had to say if the question at stake would have been proposed to him"
(p. 2783); I hereby challenge anyone to provide a calculus-like procedure
capable of finding out what this deontic counter-factual conditional requires
the interpreter to determine in each particular application of a law. (C) As
for the formal representation of disputes "until the exhaustion of the
issue", it is nothing but a diagram wherein one would see clearly how the
disputants' interventions are related to each other, i.e., what is a retort to
what, and so on; this formal structure—which it is obviously helpful to have,
synoptically, under one's eyes—addresses, however, only the 'syntax' of a
dispute, not its semantics and much less its pragmatics, which is where
'softness' is required.
I
am not questioning the fact that formal methods can be of help in handling some
aspects of the 'soft' phenomena in question. The texts I brought in to support
the imaginary (but not quite so) objections indicate how. What I consider
problematic is the suggestion that the latter can be fully accounted for by the
former. This reduction amounts to employing a process of purifying the dirty
ore into formal shining metal which in fact would suppress its value. For that
value lies precisely in the dirt, in the fact that, relatively to neat logical
form, soft rationality is essentially 'dirt'—imprecise, uncertain,
context-dependent, and therefore incapable of dispensing the exercise of human
judgment.
The very expression
'soft rationality' seems anathema when referring to the philosopher whose brand
of rationalism has been traditionally seen as solidly grounded in his
achievements in mathematics, formal logic and their applications. The idea,
however, is not to deny the presence and weight of the formal strand in
Leibniz's rationalism, but only to point out another strand, without which his
encompassing rationalism would be hardly defensible, and his rational optimism
would indeed look like a fool's fantasy. For, Voltaire's challenge can be put
this way: If this is what your 'reason' has to say about this crazy world, then
the hell with it! To which the reply is that he is right if 'reason' is nothing
more than 'radical reason'. If, however, 'soft rationality' is brought into the
picture and added to 'reason', thus filling the glass and expanding the
leibnizian conception of rationality, then, it is Candide that has no case. After
having used the expression 'soft rationality', it was brought to my attention that
Leibniz himself, in a text belonging (sic!) to VI.4's thematic category
"General Science", speaks of a "softer mode of proceeding (blandior tractandi ratio)", which
he claims to be necessary even in mathematics (p. 342). So I have reasons (soft, of course) to
believe that the picture I am here suggesting is less of a figment of my
imagination than Voltaire's Leibniz.
5. Two pictures in the same text
While there are undoubtedly texts
whose objective is obviously presenting the first of the pictures described
above, whence the other picture is virtually absent, in many texts the two
pictures—or at least elements thereof—co-exist side by side. In some of them,
one of the pictures predominates, the other playing an accessory role. Even in
these cases, however, whether one sees the non-dominant picture depends on how
strongly one is committed to a single-perspective approach. I believe that the two
pictures complement each other and neither can be completely overlooked if one
seeks to grasp the full import of any of these texts. I will try to illustrate
this by examining in some detail two texts, in each of which one of the
pictures is clearly predominant.
5.1 Recommendation
The Introduction acknowledges
Leibniz's belief in the "rationality of transmitted knowledge",
accompanied by his observation that "much effort is needed in order to
bring this rationality to light", and immediately goes on to interpret
this observation in terms of the "analyze!" injunction: "Only
that which can be understood exists before reason. And one only understands
something when its composition out of what is simpler to understand is
known" (pp. l-li). Why this jump? Why not to take into account the fact
that the effort required for properly understanding a text is, for Leibniz,
perhaps mainly due to the difficulty in interpreting
a doctrine alien to the interpreter because it is unfamiliar, ancient, or
regarding which the reader has little or no relevant contextual information and
therefore cannot "put himself in the place" of the author? In other
words, the effort required for understanding involves as much semantic as
hermeneutic skill, so that the Characteristica
Universalis analytic-semantic model
is, to say the least, insufficient without an adequate pragmatic-hermeneutic counterpart.
Consider, for
example, the Recommandation pour
instituer la science générale (pp. 692-713). Leibniz here
argues against the esprit de secte
that prevails in philosophy and stimulates competition rather than cooperation.
He urges philosophers to "imitate the geometers, who are neither
Euclidists nor Archimedists: they are all for Euclides and all for Archimedes,
because they are all for the shared master which is the divine truth" (p.
695). He recommends, especially in philosophy, the use of "an exact rigor
in reasoning" (p. 705), criticizes the "alleged demonstrations"
of Descartes and Spinoza (ibid.), defines the practice of "always looking
for reasons and expressing them distinctly with all possible precision" as
the "true method" (p. 707), and claims that, if followed, these
recommendations will "free us from the confusion of the disputes" (p.
704). These claims suggest that this text is perhaps one of the paradigmatic
examples of texts expressing nothing but the radical reason picture. Since it
is probably one of the texts Schepers had in mind in the remarks quoted in the
preceding paragraph, it might also be the one underlying the semantic-analytic
jump I pointed out.
Yet, the very same
text defends (contra Descartes) the value of the Ancients' contributions to
human knowledge, "provided they are equitably interpreted" (p. 703).
But what is an "equitable interpretation" if not one that takes into
account the constraints not only of the semantic but also of the hermeneutic
contributions to understanding? Furthermore, the very same text also stresses
those non-conclusive parts of logic that have not yet been developed, such as
probabilities, presumptions, clues and conjectures, which would be extremely
useful in practice, whenever the certainty of deductive logic cannot be
achieved (pp. 706-707).
What is more, I would
argue that Leibniz actually employs one of these kinds of non-conclusive
inferences in conceptualizing the difference between his and the Cartesian
positions and justifying his anti-Cartesian move. For what he proposes is to
re-interpret the Cartesian position that categorically demands not to accept
any proposition as true unless one has demonstrated it as a
"recommendation", i.e., as no more than a presumption. Formulated
positively, such a recommendation is equivalent to "always try to base
yourself upon reasons" (p. 703), to which Leibniz wholeheartedly
subscribes. But this no longer implies the further Cartesian demand to consider
all unproven propositions as doubtful and therefore as false, for "doubt
has nothing to do with it, since we look daily for proofs of opinions which we
do not doubt at all" (ibid.). The final step in Leibniz's argument is to
cash out this conclusion in terms of a presumption radically opposed to the
Cartesian one, albeit both are now perceived as clearly non-categorical,
namely: "the oldest and the most accepted opinions are the best, provided
one interprets them equitably"(ibid.). This radical change of attitude
towards "transmitted knowledge"—which amounts, in its turn, to taking
a definite, albeit 'soft', stand in the then raging "Querelle des Anciens
et des Modernes"—is made possible precisely by shifting from narrow to
broader criteria of "rationality", from a deductive to a presumptive
argument.
In so far as both
hermeneutics and non-deductive kinds of inference seem to lie beyond the
borders of the narrow radical reason model, we have here a text where the two
pictures co-exist side by side. Perhaps it is to their complementary role that
the Recommandation's concluding
warning also alludes: "I hold
that one should distrust reason by itself, and that it is important to have
experience or to consult those who have it" (p. 713).
5.2 Purgatory
Whereas the presence of the
alternative picture in a text belonging to the Scientia Generalis corpus may surprise some readers, its presence
in texts belonging to the other thematic categories of VI.4 is more likely to
be expected—pace the editors'
tendency to stress even in them the radical reason picture. The theology
category is a case in point. No doubt it is part of Leibniz's endeavor to
formulate a "rational theology" capable of reconciling reason and faith
and reuniting around it all Christians—or at least Western Christendom. Several
of the texts in this category are indeed guided by this aim. A particularly
interesting example is his attempt to provide an abstract definition of
'Catholic Church'—'catholic' meaning 'correct' or 'true', and hence universal.
The concept is thus reduced to two fundamental principles, love of God and
dedication to the common good: "Whoever loves God truly and strives for
the public good sincerely is truly in the Catholic Church; all the others are
schismatic" (p. 2161). These principles are sufficiently general and
uncontroversial, so that the new definition would provide the rational basis
for reunification and should command the assent of every true Christian believer—or
at least define such a believer, since Leibniz believed that there is no
"obligation to believe" (see below 6.6).
Yet, Christianity is
based not only on reason but also on the "transmitted knowledge" of a
revelation—a series of historical events preserved in non-transparent sacred
texts, whose interpretation was from the outset quite controversial. The
problem for a rational believer like Leibniz, who does not give up the
essentials of this revealed knowledge, is, then, to strike a balance between
the two components—rationality and revelation—without sacrificing either of
them. The solution of this cardinal problem requires, on the one hand, the
establishment of reasonable criteria of interpretation of the Scriptures and,
on the other, a careful consideration of the adequate model of rationality to
employ in this context. In particular, one has to ask whether the radical
reason model would not render the task impossible due to its excessive
strictures. Furthermore, since the solution must be not only intellectually
satisfactory but also politically effective in the sense of satisfying at least
the basic vested interests of the conflicting Christian factions, it is not
far-fetched to expect that, at least in some of the texts in the theology
category, the constraints of strict rationality would give way to a somewhat
softer notion of reasonableness, which in turn would render the interpretation
task easier to perform.
That Leibniz was
deeply involved in the painstaking interpretive work needed in order to deal with
controversial theological questions is well known. In VI.4, Leibniz's
hermeneutic ability is, for instance, masterfully put to use in an elaborate
discussion of the sources adduced in defense of the Catholic conception of the
purgatory, which was contested by the Protestants, especially by the Calvinists
(Consideratio locorum potissimorum quae
pro Purgatorio ex Scriptura Sacra et Sanctis patribus adducuntur—pp.
2123-2147). The Introduction mentions this text (p. lxxiv) without comment, but
I believe it deserves to be commented upon. The text is mentioned in the
context of Leibniz's efforts to provide a "rationally grounded basis"
for the debates on controversial theological issues, relying for this purpose
on his newly elaborated metaphysics (p. lxxiii). The difficulty in
understanding this rational basis is stressed and a distinction is made between
the degree of intelligibility of the proposed solution of the controversial
theological issues for which the understanding of the metaphysical "basic elements"
is sufficient and that of those issues that require the explanation of the
connection between these elements (ibid.). The former are easy issues, the
latter, difficult ones. The latter comprise the problems of human freedom and
God's grace, of God's power and how he puts it to use, the explanation of evil
in his creation, etc. They are difficult because they depend upon the
comprehensive understanding of the metaphysics of possible worlds, the complete
notion of individual substances, etc. This distinction has of course
implications for the communicative and rhetorical strategies to be adopted in
persuasively presenting and explaining "the one truth" to different
audiences.
The purgatory
doctrine is related to the theological doctrines of punishment, grace and
resurrection, thus involving both the difficult metaphysical points just
mentioned and the not easier one concerning the nature of soul and body and
their connection, so that it would presumably be classified as belonging to the
difficult side. The amount of work Leibniz devoted to this question supports
this conjecture. What is interesting, however, is that his work focuses not on
the allegedly difficult metaphysical "rationally grounded basis", but
rather on the apparently easy question of how to interpret the passages usually
quoted in the purgatory debate—a list of which, following that of Cardinal
Bellarmin who took part in this debate, Leibniz provides (pp. 2145-2147). In
his discussion, he displays his usual erudition and ingenuity, as well as an
extraordinary resourcefulness in making use of a rich and varied arsenal of
analytic, hermeneutic, and argumentative moves. It is worth examining how he
achieves in the Consideratio a rather
peculiar combination of all these tools.
The overall structure
of this text is dialectic, being determined by the Protestant opposition to the
Catholic doctrine of the purgatory—according to which the soul of a sinner,
immediately after death, is subjected to the expiation of his/her sins, so that
after being purged from them it can be admitted to beatitude (p. 2124).
Leibniz's objective is to verify whether those passages in ancient Christian
sources employed to justify this doctrine actually do it. After filtering out
the many invoked texts that are clearly irrelevant, he leaves aside also those
passages that only defend the practice of praying for the deceased (for this is
admitted by the Protestants) on the basis of the dialectical principle that
"it is useless to prove that which is conceded" by the opponent (p.
2126). The same principle allows him to omit those passages that can be
understood as referring to the "purgatory of resurrection", for
"the Protestants concede a great deal" of this doctrine. As we shall
see, passages of the latter kind are not omitted at all. In fact, Leibniz's
main strategy in the Consideratio
turns out to be an attempt to show, for as many of the adduced passages as
possible, that they justify this second kind of purgatory but not the first
one.
Since the exegesis of
the passages will turn on the distinction between the two kinds of purgatory,
Leibniz first puts to use his analytic skills in defining precisely the first
and then highlighting the second's contrasting features vis-à-vis it.
"Purgatory I" is defined as "the place or state of believers'
souls in which, immediately after death, they expiate for some time their sins
with severe torments and are helped by the living's prayers and sacrifices in
order to be admitted, once divine justice is placated, into beatitude even
before resurrection" (p. 2126). "Purgatory II", by contrast,
takes place after resurrection
(rather than immediately after death and before resurrection). It concerns
"the whole man after the re-connection of soul and body" (rather than
the separate souls alone), and is universal, i.e. applies to everyone (rather
than only to particular sinners) albeit with different duration and intensity
(p. 2127). Both purgatories are temporary states and in both fire and its
cognates figure prominently.
In the light of these
contrastive and shared elements, passages that speak only of temporary
expiation after death, of fire and of purgation are not specific enough as
proof of Purgatory I. Therefore, they can be treated as referring to Purgatory
II, being thus irrelevant to the Catholic-Protestant dispute. Consequently,
Leibniz declares that they are not going to be considered in the Consideratio, for he does not want to
bring up passages "that are so easy for the Protestants to reject"
(ibid.). As a neutral and objective analyst and judge of the controversy, he
applies thus the dialectical/juridical principle according to which the
"opponent" must prove his point by confronting the hardest—not the
easiest—pieces of counter-evidence. Another clarification he makes of the notion
of Purgatory II might, instead, favor the Protestants. Consider the possible
objection that this notion is contrary to divine justice, since its universal
application implies that the pious and the impious alike, after having been judged by God, are subjected to the fire of
Purgatory II. If admitted, this incongruence would prevent the Protestants from
relying on this notion as they do. Leibniz comes to their help by reporting
that the tradition distinguishes (a typical disputatio
move employed to duck an objection) between two kinds of fire—a purifying and
benefic one (for the pious) and a soiling and excruciating one (for the
damned). The former is further explained through an analogy: it acts upon the
pious like the heat of a high furnace acts upon gold by making it more
beautiful (p. 2127).
The framework set,
Leibniz gets down to the task of examining in detail the passages that pass the
relevance test. In each case, the presumption that the passage proves the
existence of Purgatory I is weighed against evidence for interpreting it in
terms of Purgatory II. Obviously, such a tactic only makes sense within the
dialectical macro-structure of the whole text. But a variety of moves, based on
different dialectical and hermeneutic principles, are employed for its implementation.
Consider a few
examples. Of the many passages from Origen adduced, all but one are dismissed
as interpretable in terms of Purgatory II. In the passage making the exception,
however, Origen is shown to reduce Hell to Purgatory, which makes this passage
unreliable, for it does not preserve an established distinction (p. 2128).
Tertullian's expression 'the jail of hell' is taken to mean
"purgatory", but it might mean "hell" tout court (p. 2130). However, the fact that this expression
appears in a sentence explaining that sinners are there jailed until
"later resurrection" (mora
resurrectionis) dispels this
ambiguity for it points to temporary punishment rather than to eternal
damnation. Nevertheless, mora
resurrectionis is itself a "quite obscure" expression (p. 2131).
A very detailed syntactic, semantic and contextual analysis of this expression
follows, leading to different possible meanings, all bearing on whether 'the
jail of hell' means Purgatory I or not. The chosen meaning is the one supporting
a positive answer; this is the meaning also favored by Cyprian, a disciple of
Tertullian who "usually respects and follows his teacher" (p. 2132).
Nevertheless, this reliance on Cyprian's endorsement does not prevent Leibniz
from criticizing Cyprian's own passage—another of the sources adduced—for the
"many doubts" that plague it, which preoccupied Roman Catholic
authors. After analyzing such doubts, Leibniz concludes by attributing to
Cyprian a distinction his passage must presuppose, "unless we want to admit
that he wrote confusedly" (ibid.)—a nicely formulated use of the
"principle of communicative charity". And so on and so forth.
In order to get the
feel of the subtle details of Leibniz's deliberative argumentation, let us
pause for a slightly longer look at his considerations about what can be
learned from Basilius. To begin with, his reference to Isaiah 4 is claimed to
refer to Purgatory II, for he explicitly says that the Lord's
"examination" (mentioned by the prophet) of the sins of the daughters
of Sion in view of their eventual absolution is actually performed through
"the fire of the judgment" and "the heat or boiling of the
judgment" (ibid.). This not only means that the examination takes place at
a stage of afterlife—presumably the "final judgment"—which is well
beyond the immediacy of death, but also strongly suggests a literal reading of
'fire', which would be inconsistent with the metaphorical reading implicit in
Purgatory I, since souls without bodies cannot be literally affected by "fire".
Leibniz admits that he was first inclined to accept the objection that
'judgment' need not be understood here as "final judgment", for it
could refer to any examination,
including the one that no doubt takes place in Purgatory I (p. 2129). Against
this, however, Basilius' further claim, still in the context of Isaiah 4, that
the judgment in question occurs "in a future century"—a phrase that
usually refers to the final judgment—is decisive (p. 2130). Leibniz singles out
another passage of Basilius, this time referring to Isaiah 6. Part of this
passage interprets the "burning coal", which an angel picks up from
the altar with fire-tongs in order to touch Isaiah's lips thereby purifying
him, as acting upon his soul, thus supporting Purgatory I; another part, however,
might be seen as stressing the corporeal effect of the fire that "inflames
the heart" of sinners, thus apparently inclining towards Purgatory II. The
authority of Paul's passage on the straw and salvation "as if through
fire", whose 'as if' fits the Purgatory I reading, is brought into the
discussion and perhaps is the decisive factor for Leibniz's conclusion that
this passage ultimately supports Purgatory I. Commenting on Procopius Gazaeus,
who "seems to have had Basilius's words in front of his eyes" (p.
2129) and interprets him as favoring Purgatory I, Leibniz argues that this
author inconsistently mixed up the two passages, so that his interpretation is
useless (p. 2130). The conclusion of all this is that only one of Basilius'
passages, namely, the one in Isaiah 6, can be plausibly understood as referring
to Purgatory I. Yet, how much plausibility there is to it? Well, certainly not
much, given Leibniz's own doubts and hesitations, the unreliability of earlier
interpretations of Basilius, the veiled appeal to authority, and the shaky
grounds for deciding between literal and metaphorical readings.
However weak the
grounds for the conclusion reached turn out to be, the elaborate process of
careful and detailed weighing of the reasons pro and con a purported
interpretation of a passage is not otiose. First, because it leads, after all,
to a conclusion—albeit a merely plausible one (remember what the inability of
deciding in favor of one or the other heap of straw did to Buridan's poor
ass!). Second, because it seems to be the only possible way of performing the
exegetical task. And finally, because whoever has followed the argumentation
cannot but be fully aware of the strengths and weaknesses of the conclusion
reached, i.e., of the approximate relative weight to be assigned to it in the
final step of deciding about the main issue discussed in the text, namely,
whether the current Catholic doctrine of Purgatory I is supported by good
ancient textual evidence.
It is not surprising, therefore, that at one point, after
summarizing the conclusions that can be drawn from the passages discussed so
far, and pointing out that the scales tend to support Purgatory I, especially
due to the clear statements of Augustin and others in this direction, he adds
that "the issue is not completely clear", and goes on to express his
wonderment as to how far it has been left hanging [by the Ancients] who often
kept silent about the purgatory, when the occasion demanded that they talk most
and clearly about it. His conjecture is that this shows that the doctrine was
not sufficiently established at that time (p. 2139), presumably because it
developed later. In any case, "the Ancients did not talk about the things
of the other world we today assert—and this is certain" (p. 2140). What is
surprising is that, in spite of all the careful weighing, the cautiously hedged
formulations he had been using all along, and the general difficulty in
understanding the Ancients' views on the other world, Leibniz concludes
categorically: "The Ancients would unanimously condemn anyone who claimed
that the prayers for the dead are useless and that all souls are either
immediately saved or immediately damned" (p. 2140). This is a wonderfully
crafted statement that deserves, per se, exegesis, but the reader by now might
be weary of this. Let me just say that this syntactically
double conditional, which is semantically
a hypothetical statement—perhaps even a counterfactual, seems to have been pragmatically very precisely worded in
order to fulfill a specific dialectical role:
to have the full authority of the Fathers of the Church anachronistically
condemning … the Calvinists! (Foucher de Careil saw in the earlier Confessio Philosophi of 1673 the expression
of "Leibniz's victory over Calvinism", a view Yvon Belaval rejects on
the grounds that Leibniz did not want to defeat Calvinism, but rather to
reconcile it with Lutheranism; see Belaval's introduction to the Confessio,
pp. 14-15.)
The
punch line aside, it is clear that, of the two pictures, the one that stars in
this text is certainly not the "radical reason" model.
To be sure, there is
plenty of linguistic and conceptual analysis, necessary for rendering the
passages considered sufficiently intelligible for the argumentation to proceed.
But obviously the analysis falls short of reaching the level of primitive
concepts. Definitions are reached, to be sure, but they are at best of the type
Leibniz will call in the Meditationes
'nominal', which provide only distinctive
features of the definiendum. No 'real'
definitions are within reach, so that none of the key concepts can be even
proven to be contradiction-free and thus possible. Consequently, no
formalization is sought that would permit a calculus-like procedure to be
applied so as to compellingly and finally decide the issues.
To be sure, the laws
of logic are respected: invalid inferences and inconsistencies are to be
avoided. Yet, since logic alone is insufficient to yield the interpretations
sought, other principles of inference—pragmatic, hermeneutic, dialectic—are
also used. They include, as we have seen, the logic-related (but not reducible
to logic) requirement of intra- and inter-textual coherence (eliminating
inconsistencies and "accommodating" one passage with the others as
well as with authoritative traditions—p. 2130), as well as the rhetorically
effective ad hominem and ad verecundiam arguments, the dialectic
distribution of the charge of proof, and the pragmatic maxims underlying the
assignment to a speaker of metaphorical or implicit meanings. In fact, a few
lines before the end, Leibniz both makes a pragmatic inference and warns
against the uncertainty inbuilt in such inferences. Having argued that in one
passage the Archbishop of Caesarea, Arethas, tacitly avoids an implication (that all martyrs are immediately
saved upon their death), Leibniz points out the impossibility of generalizing
this conclusion on the basis of a single obscure and controversial passage:
"I don't dare to affirm anything certain about this, especially since, if one
takes into account the connection between words, it appears that another sense
can also emerge" (p. 2144). In current pragmatic
jargon, he would state this as the principle according to which attributions of
implicit intentions to a speaker or author are essentially co-text and context sensitive—which makes them reliable
only in a case by case basis. Involving as they do all these non-logical
principles, the core of the Consideratio's
arguments cannot be subsumed under the label 'demonstrative' without further
ado.
The text is no doubt
conscientiously systematic. But its systematicity does not follow the axiomatic
model. It is rather that typical of disputation, i.e. dialectical in nature.
Its basic procedure is that of a deliberation in which reasons favorable and
contrary to a purported conclusion are weighed against each other until a
decision is (or is not) reached—a decision that remains, however, tentative and
contestable in the light of further considerations.
Nevertheless, there
can be no doubt that a text such as this (as well as similar ones in law,
politics, medicine and other domains where interpretive work is essential)
instantiates what—if anything—can be called "rational discourse". But
in order to grasp its rationality one has to transcend the narrow domain of
'radical reason' and see that what, from the point of view of this model,
appears as weaknesses are in fact, from the point of view of a 'softer' model
of rationality, strengths that permit reason to apply to a much broader range
of human endeavors. It would seem that, in theology, softer rational procedures
like the ones displayed in the Consideratio—and
it is not the only example thereof—cannot be replaced by stricter ones, which
can at most complement them. In so far as this text of the beginning of 1677
must be seen as part of the "Catholic Demonstrations" ambitious
project Leibniz elaborated already in Mainz—which according to the Introduction
informs his work also in Hanover—it seems necessary to conclude that the word
'demonstration' in such a project cannot be reduced to its radical reason model
reading.
5. A three-pronged breakthrough
As already pointed out, in 1686
Leibniz writes three of the most elaborate and significant texts of the period
covered by VI.4—one in logic, one in metaphysics, one in theology. He expressly
manifests his feeling of significant progress in one of them, but he certainly
felt similarly regarding the other two as well. It is beyond the scope of the
present paper to spell out in detail the precise nature of the breakthrough in
each of these fields. After an overview of each, I will rather discuss three
topics they deal with—which will permit me to address the question, raised
above (2.4), of whether and how the progress made in these fields is related.
My suggestion is that the answer cannot be given solely in terms of any one of
the pictures we have been discussing, but requires taking into account the
interplay between them.
5.1 General Inquiries
The "General inquiries about
the analysis of concepts and of truths" (pp. 739-788) is a complex and
extremely rich text about which much has been written, though no consensus
about why Leibniz was so fond of it emerges from the commentaries. The
philosophical cornerstone of the text is Leibniz's 'analytic' theory of truth,
according to which in every true proposition the predicate is contained in the
subject. The purpose is to implement this theory by formal means. The strictly
formal approach reaches a high level of generality, for it seeks to develop an
abstract calculus whose variables can be interpreted as concepts as well as
propositions and whose axioms can serve to analyze (i.e., to 'prove' or
'demonstrate') both and to account for the widest possible range of inferences.
In this respect, it goes beyond the Characteristica
Universalis, whose 'characters' are not only formal but 'material' (in the
sense of traditional logic), i.e., semantically interpreted symbols. One of the sets of axioms in the Generales Inquisitiones, to which the
Introduction calls attention (p. lxi)—and which may have particularly pleased
Leibniz—boldly purports to capture entirely the notion of 'formal validity' (vis formae). Its seventh and last axiom is a completeness
clause stating that "whatever cannot be demonstrated from these principles,
does not follow by virtue of [logical] form (vi formae)" (p. 785). In spite of being incomplete and
consisting in a not quite systematic sequence of attempts to develop complete
axiomatic systems, the Generales
Inquisitiones can be rightly seen as the flagship of the radical reason
picture, where traces of the softer picture are difficult—but not impossible—to
find.
5.2 Discourse on
Metaphysics
The "Discourse on
metaphysics" (pp. 1529-1588), conceived as a concise summary to be
submitted to Arnauld's examination, is in fact the first comprehensive
formulation of Leibniz's mature metaphysics. The Introduction describes it as a
"grandiose" and "masterfully" organized work, containing
"unheard of" new ideas (p. lxviii). It introduces indeed the notion
of the complete concept of an individual substance—the basis of what Leibniz
later called 'monad'. This notion, in conjunction with the principle of maximum
perfection of God (hence, of the created universe) and of the analytic
conception of truth, yields most of his well-known metaphysical theses. Leibniz
believes his system solves several crucial metaphysical and theological
problems—e.g., the body-mind relation, the creation, causality, evil, divine
grace. He is particularly proud to have found a way out of the "labyrinth
of freedom", i.e., the notoriously difficult centuries-old problem of
overcoming the apparent antinomy between human freedom and divine providence
(or determinism), as well as between God's freedom and his rationality. The key
to this solution is the new way he proposes of accounting for the fundamental
distinction between necessary and contingent truths, which will be discussed
below.
5.3 Examination of
the Christian Religion
The "Examination of the
Christian religion", originally untitled, is "the most comprehensive
text of this volume" (introductory note, p. 2356). It is also the longest
(pp. 2356-2455). It undertakes to examine the ensemble of the Catholic dogmas,
but is abruptly interrupted in the midst of a sentence and therefore does not
fulfill its plan in its entirety. Among other things, it does not discuss the
extremely controversial issue of papal primacy and authority, about which it at
one point promises to "say much later".
The text was
presumably intended to carry out the earlier plan, submitted in 1683 to Count
von Hessen-Rheinfels, of writing an "Exposition of the Faith" dealing
with some controversial points, a text which would be approved by the new Pope
Innocence XI. Prior to further diffusion and publication, the text would be
sent to "moderate bishops" in order to check its
"tolerability" by the Church and, upon their approval, to
About a century after
its composition Catholic theologians realized the value of this text for them,
and hastened to publish the manuscript, which received several editions in the
course of the 19th century. The editor of one of these editions,
which contains other texts as well (Exposition
de la Doctrine de Leibniz sur la Religion, Paris, 1819), M. Emery, General
Superior of St. Sulpice, understood "what an interest for the
Catholics" this "religious testament" of a man that all his life
was concerned with "the points of doctrine separating Catholics and Protestants"
held (p. i). Another Catholic scholar, who apparently was in charge of
preparing the Examination for
publication (under the title "Theological System") in the same volume,
spells this interest out, by saying that in this work, which "would make
more sensation than all other writings of Leibnitz", he "defends with
so much zeal the Catholic religion, even on those points that have been most
vividly debated between Catholics and Protestants, that one could hardly
believe he was its author" (id., p. xix). Alas! The Catholic
acknowledgment Leibniz needed for his reunification endeavors came too late.
I mention these
details because they are important for understanding the dialectical context to
which the Examination belongs and,
thereby, its mode of argumentation, structure, contents, and even its political
failure. Even a hundred years later, the interest Catholic readers attached to
this "Catholic" text resides in its having been written by a Lutheran, who had no intention whatsoever to convert.
Looking at the text alone, one might perhaps be fooled by its professed
neutrality and objectivity, regardless of the author's identity. But for the
active participants in the ongoing negotiations in Leibniz's time, it was
impossible not to see this text as what it really was: a move by one of the
parties involved. To be sure, the Introduction describes the circumstances and
explains, in terms of them, why the move failed. But it goes on to comment on
the text's contents, setting aside these circumstances, which it views as
"external". This purely semantic approach, which is part and parcel
of the 'radical reason' picture, is what leads it to emphasize—as in other
cases—those virtues of the text that fit such a picture, overlooking its not
less significant pragmatic-dialectic virtues which the other picture,
naturally, would highlight.
Accordingly, the Examination is praised for its use of
the "method of exclusion" that mandates the uncompromising rejection
of undisputable errors of various sects, for the terminological rigor and
clarity that avoids verbal disputes, for the systematic organization of the
material in view of the aim it pursues, and above all for choosing "right
reason" (recta ratio) as the supreme
examining authority (p. lxxviii). The Introduction acknowledges that this text
purports to provide a basic platform for the reunification negotiations
(ibid.), but points out that it does not follow the usual dialectical position
vs. position and move vs. counter-move pattern of writings prepared for
particular reunification "colloquia" (p. lxxviii). Instead, it
displays a quasi-axiomatic demonstrative order, which begins with a consensual
general definition of God and unfolds its consequences up to the justification
of the sacraments and mysteries of faith (ibid.). It is this distancing from
the circumstantial in search for rational foundations that grants a text like
this a place in a volume of "Philosophical" rather than
"Political" writings (p. lx). The question is how large is the
distance, i.e., how far can one decontextualize the Examination, ignoring its dialectical underpinnings, and still
understand it properly.
The text is no doubt
systematic. It starts with the notion of God, the sources of knowledge, the
nature of theological discourse and truth; and then proceeds stepwise to deal
with specific doctrinal points such as trinity, Christology, incarnation,
sanctification, cult, idolatry, the appeal to saints, the use of relics, the
sacraments, the mass; with organizational matters such as priesthood, celibacy
and Church hierarchy; with eschatology, e.g., the purgatory, the nature of
beatitude, resurrection—and this is not an exhaustive list. A concise list of
the theses Leibniz argues for (which he himself partially provided in the
coetaneous text "Positions"; pp. 2351-2354) shows that neither the
list of topics nor their order is casual. It contains, in particular, the
principal points of contention raised by the Protestants. The
"positions", thus, are in fact answers to well-known Protestant
arguments, but they cannot transgress
The dialectical nature
of this situation imposes upon Leibniz's recta
ratio a situatedness that severely constrains its freedom of operation.
This self-appointed mediator, who in fact is an active participant by
intervening as he does in the debate, knows very well that neither he nor
anyone else can pretend he is landing from an outer world wherefrom he brings
to bear upon issues that have been hotly debated and fought about for so long
the irresistible wisdom of a "view from nowhere". The author of the Examination is well aware that the ethos
he projects in the opening paragraph is problematic, since it comprises
conflicting elements: the 'natural', uncorrupted reason of a
"neophyte" as if just arrived from the new world, the neutrality of
"as much as humanly possible non-partisanship", and the experience
with religious controversies of someone who is "well-versed" in them.
It seems to me that the main philosophical interest of this text lies not in
opting for one of these components, to the exclusion or minimization of the
others, but rather in attempting to strike a balance between them.
6.4 Inclining without
necessitating
Focusing now on a few specific
points briefly mentioned in the preceding sub-sections, let us consider first
the necessary/contingent distinction. Both necessary and contingent truths must
of course be analytic, according to Leibniz's theory of truth. The distinction
between them is made, in the Generales
Inquisitiones, in terms of the quasi-mathematical distinction between
"perfect" and "imperfect" or "finite" and
"infinite" analysis. "A true necessary proposition can be proved
by reduction to identical propositions", whereas a true contingent
proposition cannot be thus reduced and "is proved by showing that if the
analysis is continued further and further, it constantly approaches identical
propositions, but never reaches them". Epistemologically, the latter kind
of proof "transcends every finite intellect" and "God alone, who
grasps the entire infinite in his mind, knows all contingent truths with certainty".
Logically, such a proof yields only 'certainty' but not 'necessity', because
the proposition thus proved "can never be reduced to an identical
proposition or its opposite to a contradictory proposition" (pp. 775-776;
Parkinson's transl.).
In the Discours de Metaphysique the distinction
necessary/contingent acquires, in addition, an ontological dimension. Paragraph
13 of the Discours, the one Arnauld
reacted to most negatively, concludes by explaining the difference in terms of
the opposition between two realms—that of possibilities and that of existence.
The former concerns "the essences themselves"; the latter, "what
is or seems to be the best among different equally possible things". The
former is ruled by the principle of contradiction, the latter by "the
principle of contingency or of the existence of things" (p. 1549); while
the former governs the realm of the possible, the latter does not affect it (p.
1548), since its violation does not imply impossibility. The dichotomy finite vs.
infinite analysis is neither the definitional criterion nor the reason for the
different modal operators ('necessary' or 'certain') attached to necessary and
contingent truths. What is decisive are rather the grounds for their respective
proofs. The proof that the individual substance 'Caesar' has the predicate
'crosses the Rubicon at t' "is not as absolute as" a geometric
demonstration because it presupposes certain "free divine decrees"
(such as "I will always do that which is most perfect" and
"humans will always freely do that which seems the best"). Decrees
such as these are certain because, although they might be violated in some possible world, in the actually created
maximally perfect world they are not.
If their opposites do not materialize, "it is not [due to] their
impossibility but [to] their imperfection". Consequently, "every
truth that is grounded on this kind of decree is contingent, though
certain" (p. 1548). A contingent truth is thus 'weaker' than a necessary
one because it relies upon premises or principles that have the status of
presumptions, i.e., that can be in principle denied without contradiction. This
is why the reasons they provide only "incline
without necessitating" (p. 1548).
Like any presumption, they and their consequences can be overruled,
provided reasons for this are produced, the burden of proof being always upon
he who attempts to overrule them. They are, however, very well-grounded
presumptions that provide "strong reasons" (rationes fortes; p. 806), so that it is very hard to find
overruling reasons—which is why these principles, and the conclusions they
ground, are 'certain'. Nevertheless, they remain presumptive or 'hypothetical'
truths—as Leibniz dubs them.
As far as I know, the
locution incliner sans necessiter is
a terminological innovation of the Discours
de Metaphysique and coetaneous texts (e.g., "The principle of human
science", pp. 670-672; "On the primary principles of contradiction
and of sufficient reason", pp. 803-806), but I leave it to the reader to
check more attentively than I perhaps did the Subject Index. In any case,
Leibniz's later recurrent use of this locution indicates the undisputable
pivotal role the status of contingent truths it expresses acquires henceforth
in his metaphysics and theology. In the Discours
itself (paragraph 30), for example, God's alleged responsibility for human sins
is explained away on the grounds that he "inclines"—as strongly as
"determining"—our will towards the choice of what appears as the
best, without however "necessitating" it to actually choose in this
way, so that we remain free to choose and the responsibility for our choices
and actions is, ultimately, not his but ours. And in the Théodicée, what is perhaps the most important
argumentative strategy employed against Bayle consists in showing that the
reasons he adduces against such a presumption are not powerful enough.
The recourse to the
notion of inclination immediately—and
deliberately, I believe—brings to mind the image of the scales used at the
time—the model for what Leibniz elsewhere called "scales of reason" (trutina rationis; cf. A VI 1, pp. 548ff.),
i.e., scales where reasons for and
against a conclusion or decision are weighed.
This procedure, in contrast to the decision
procedure provided by a formal calculus or demonstration, rarely if ever leads to a necessary and incontestable result. Nevertheless, it can and, if
properly conducted does, lead to a reasonable
one, i.e., sufficient to opt rationally for one of the scales—the one toward
which the combined weight of the reasons incline,
albeit this option may be turned upside down if other reasons are later brought
up. This metaphor is a central topos of the 'soft reason' picture. Its implicit
presence in the Discours, and the key
role the notion it helps to conceptualize plays in this text, can therefore be
a sure indicator not only of the presence but also of the importance the
picture in question has in Leibniz's mature metaphysics. Furthermore, the fact
that he unabashedly makes use of a metaphorical locution to express the
distinctive feature of a fundamental notion such as contingent truth, reveals
the presence of another typically 'soft reason' trait in the Discours, namely the need—perhaps
unavoidable—to employ metaphors and analogies in order to convey novel concepts
that transcend the dichotomies embedded in traditional philosophical
discourse—which is what Leibniz's account of contingency undertakes to do.
But—one may suggest—cannot this metaphor be, in fact, easily cashed out in
formal terms?
This is precisely
what the Introduction, in the wake of Leibniz's own pronouncements, suggests.
The Introduction repeatedly argues (e.g., on pages lxii, lxv, lxx) that
Leibniz, the creator of a calculus that successfully deals operationally with
infinitesimal magnitudes, surely possesses the means for providing a
non-metaphorical account of contingent truths, namely, the notion of an
"infinite analysis" of a proposition. In fact, this is precisely what
he seems to claim in the Generales
Inquisitiones, as we have seen. The Introduction's claim, however,
overlooks the fact that, after introducing this notion and stating that
"the distinction between necessary and contingent truths is the same (idem) as that between lines which meet
and asymptotes, or between commensurable and incommensurable numbers" (p.
776), Leibniz warns against taking this statement too literally. For, if so
taken it would imply more than what it actually yields: "We can prove that
some line—namely, an asymptote—constantly approaches another, and (also in the
case of asymptotes) we can prove that two quantities are equal, by showing what
will be the case if the progression is continued as far as one pleases; so
human beings will be able to comprehend contingent truths with certainty. But
it must be replied that there is indeed a likeness (similitude) here, but there is not a complete agreement (convenientia)" (p. 776; Parkinson
translation). So, what the mathematics of the infinite provides for
understanding contingent truths is a handy and suggestive analogy, viz. a
metaphor, which breaks down precisely because it cannot offer the tools for
actually computing or proving such truths.
Leibniz adds what
seems to be a possible explanation for this breakdown of the analogy, namely,
the existence of "relations (respectus)
which, however far an analysis is continued, will never reveal themselves
sufficiently for certainty, and are seen perfectly only by him whose intellect
is infinite" (ibid.). If we recall that the complete analysis of a
contingent truth would require referring to an individual substance's relations
with all other individual substances and to the result of the global comparison between all other
possible worlds in order to determine that the created world is the most
perfect one, we have a glimpse at why such an analysis involves a complexity that only God can actually
grasp and deal with. Even Leibniz was aware that, however suggestive his
analogy, there was a leap—perhaps unbridgeable—between the proven powers of his
mathematics of the infinite and the tools necessary to fully unfold,
analytically, the grounds of contingency. The trust he often expresses that
posterity will be able to do what he and his contemporaries couldn't do is of
no avail to him here, for at least to this day the mathematics of complexity is
very far from providing the tools the "infinite analysis" of
contingent truths need. Perhaps in this domain we face the limits of the
capabilities of formal thought. In any case, in his time this metaphor couldn't
be cashed out formally, and therefore to appeal to it in support of the
'radical reason' picture is rather like appealing to a Trojan horse.
6.5 Human knowledge
The Discours de Metaphysique locates human beings at the top of
creation (paragraph 35; pp. 1584-1586), as the creatures closest to the
creator. The "principle of Arlequin" establishes that
"everywhere and at all times things are like they are at our place and
now" (GP, III, p. 340). The principle of continuity precludes gaps of any
sort, for their existence would imply imperfection. Nevertheless, a profound
ontological gap and a deep difference separate God from us, humans—the gap
between absolute perfection and whatever is less than that. If proof is needed
of its existence, recall Leibniz's speculations about the existence of a host
of non-corporeal species of spirits filling the gap between the human species
and God (GP, VI, p. 548). This ontological gap has crucial epistemological
consequences. The impossibility for humans to perform the infinite analysis
that would formally prove contingent truths is one of its manifestations.
Lacking God's epistemological perfections, humans must endeavor to reach
whatever knowledge they are capable to achieve by employing less than perfect
means. They need to develop 'helps'—to use Bacon's expression—to overcome as
much as possible their limitations and to make the knowledge they achieve as
sure and reliable as possible.
In
fact, the search for methods of proof that culminates in the idea of
formalization is a search for helps God does not need but men do, even in order
to secure knowledge of those truths—the necessary truths—which are not in
principle beyond human reach. For an analysis and a calculus that yield the
knowledge of these truths to work, an adequate notation is essential—a notation
obeying what Leibniz calls the 'law of expression': "in the same way that
the idea of a thing to be expressed is composed of the ideas of the things that
compose it, the symbol (character) expressing the thing must be composed of the
symbols of its components" (p. 916). Without such a notation we couldn't
go far, due to the limited capacity of what psychologists call our 'short term
memory'—namely, the amount of information we can keep simultaneously under our
focus of attention. With its help, however, we are able to compress and code
the information into symbols, which relieve our mind from the need to be aware,
each time we think of a thing or concept, of the myriad of its components. This
is what Leibniz calls, in the Meditationes,
'blind' or 'symbolic' thought (pp. 587-588). This is not to be understood as a
pejorative denomination, for it is what increases significantly our cognitive
capacity, even though if compared to God's capacity of grasping "at one
glance" (uno obtutu) the whole
complexity of the universe, it remains insignificant.
If
notational helps are essential ingredients in our formal, demonstrative
methods, semiotic and other means of organizing our quest for knowledge are
even more needed in those parts of the Scientia
Generalis, belonging to the "art of discovery", which are of an
informal, heuristic nature: a well-ordered (not necessarily 'demonstrative')
encyclopedia; synopses in the form of summaries, lists, tables, or diagrams,
etc. Such tools as the encyclopedia, cooperatively and painstakingly developed
bottom-up from the knowledge available at a given time, not only suggest to us
what is missing and ought to be discovered or elaborated henceforth; they also
allow us to rise a few inches above the ground in our efforts to see 'the big
picture' that God, at the top, has always so easily in front of his eyes. Even
the imperfect—because historically evolved—grammatical and semantic structure
of natural languages can—with the help of some systematization—provide a useful
thread for helping us to see, uno obtutu,
"the entire variety of what is thinkable" (pp. 594-604).
Leibniz
incorporated in the text of the Discours
the contents of two of the three papers he published in this period which are
included in VI.4: the "Brief demonstration of a memorable error of
Descartes" (1686; pp. 2027-2030), in paragraph 17 (pp. 1556-1558) and the
"Meditations on cognition, truth and ideas" (1684; pp. 585-592), in
paragraphs 24 and 25 (pp. 1567-1570). While in the former he employs a
mathematical demonstration in order to prove the mistake in question, thereby
purporting to show the need to introduce "final causes" in physics,
in the latter he elaborates a theory of knowledge that acknowledges the value
even of obscure and non-distinct ideas as forms of 'knowledge', as well as the
indispensability of 'blind thought'. Except for a few cases in which we are
able to know something through direct access to the relevant concept's complete
analysis—a type of knowledge he calls 'intuitive' –, in the vast majority of
cases, we have to rely upon what he in the Discours
he calls 'suppositive' knowledge, since for even mildly complex notions we must
content ourselves with presupposing their analysis to be given. From the point
of view of an epistemology dealing with a limited mind like ours, no source of
knowledge and no kind of help can be neglected. All fall short of an
unachievable divine ideal, and all—demonstrative and inclining alike—are
mentioned in the same tree of types of knowledge of the Meditationes, and appear next to each other in the same text, as it
happens in the Discours.
If
mild complexity already poses problems for human cognition, the huge complexity
of the entire world, which underlies every contingent truth, only magnifies it.
As we have seen, we are unable to unveil all the details of this extremely
complex structure and thereby give a full analytic explanation of each
proposition. Were we to take this as a reason for giving up the attempt to
discover at least some of the regularities and order that govern the world, we
would be like credulous creatures that take the shortcut of seeing miracles
everywhere as the only explanation of what happens in a fundamentally
disordered and irregular world. What helps us out is, first, to realize that
regularity and order, even in geometry, is not always simple: if a straight
line does not connect a series of points, it may simply be due to the fact that
they are connected by a more complex line rather than arbitrarily juxtaposed,
for "when a rule is very complex what fits it may pass for irregular"
(Discours, paragraph 6; p. 1538).
Epistemologically, this teaches us to adopt a presumption of regularity rather than of irregularity and search
harder for the former before giving up to the mere appearance of the latter.
For Leibniz this practical maxim, which allows us to pursue our scientific
endeavors, is grounded on the general presumption of the order and rationality
of a world created by a perfect being, to which even real miracles—whose
existence he, as a believer, cannot deny—are subordinated. At most, he
contends, miracles violate "subaltern" laws, but fit the
"general order" (Discours,
paragraph 7; p. 1538). Nevertheless, the fact that not even admitted
miracles—whose underlying "rule" we cannot find—do not violate the
general presumption of rationality, only shows how strong and well justified
this presumption is, and how useful it is as such in our search for knowledge.
But, however strong, it remains a presumption. No doubt it yields a powerful epistemological
guideline or 'help', which, in spite of its force, only inclines without
necessitating. Still, it is its generality and power that ranks it—or the
principle upon which it is grounded, namely "that there is nothing without
a reason" (quod nihil est sine
ratione)—"among the highest and most fecund [axioms] of all human
cognition, upon which most of metaphysics, of physics and of moral science are
erected" (p. 806).
Within
the full range of epistemological 'helps' at our disposal, the formal ones
favored by the 'radical reason' model cover only a small portion of the whole
realm of knowledge, most of which requires 'softer' forms of rationality.
Although these formal helps are not free of imperfection, the neatness and
certainty they provide entice one to see in them the ideal to be pursued
everywhere. This ideal did indeed entice Leibniz, and he ceaselessly worked
toward its realization—as the texts in VI.4 abundantly testify. But he never
overlooked the need to develop also the 'softer' helps, even at the height of
his formalistic drive. As his system crystallized in the breakthrough year of
1686, the formal and the informal, the hard and the softer, the necessitating
and the inclining epistemological tools found their respective places and raison d'être, side by side,
within the global perspective of a 'system'. Had VI.4 'epistemology' as a
thematic category—under which perhaps the Scientia
Generalis category should be subsumed rather than vice-versa—this global
picture would have become synoptically visible for the reader.
6.6 Persuading without obligating
Referring to "On the
obligation to believe" (pp. 2149-2155), one of the earliest texts of the
period covered by VI.4, the Introduction comments that it "provides a
paradigm of what Leibniz understands by a demonstration" (p. lxxvi). No
doubt this text—elaborated through various versions, whose conclusion is that
"there is no obligation to believe, but only to investigate with utmost
application" (p. 2154)—displays a paradigmatic demonstrative form, with
its definitions, lemmas, theorems and even the result of an
"experiment" (p. 2153). But there is a catch.
The text has a
peculiar subtitle that suggests that Leibniz was not so eager to consider it as
exemplifying a particularly unproblematic or praiseworthy demonstration, namely
Ratiocinatio quae pro demonstratione
venditatur. This can be interpreted either as commending the
"reasoning" the text presents as amounting to a demonstration, or
else as mocking its appearance of a demonstration—two possibilities the
standard figurative readings of the frequentative verb vendito ('to offer again and again for sale') permit. The editors
seem to have opted for the former reading; I am rather inclined towards the
latter. After all, the virtue of a good demonstration is that its formal force
shows itself and need not be advertised as such, so that the subtitle in fact
hedges the reasoning's pretense to be a demonstration. The erased phrase mihi communicata ('communicated to me')
next to ratiocinatio indeed indicates
that Leibniz distances himself, for some reason, from this 'demonstration'. The
reason cannot be the conclusion, which expresses a view Leibniz holds and whose
first part at least is in full consonance with the Lutheran thesis that faith
cannot be imposed being rather a gift of God. Nor is it some formal defect.
A hint at what the
reason for his qualms may be is given by Leibniz himself, in the following
erased passage: "Nothing can be objected to this demonstration if the
definitions I have given are followed. If, however, someone does not admit
them, the dispute ends, for [the opponent] thereby declares he employs the
words obligation, to believe etc. in a sense different
from the one I attribute to them. As for myself, I declare that I am satisfied
with demonstrating the proposition according to the sense I have assumed the
words have—which I think is not different from their ordinary usage" (p.
2154). His definitions, however, are rather unusual, as Grua (p. 181n) remarked
about the definition of 'obligation' as "a necessity imposed under the
fear of a just punishment". The same could be said of the definition of
'believing' as "being conscious of [the] reasons that persuade us"
(p. 2152). The usefulness of a demonstration—especially for the 'analytic'
Leibniz—depends upon the definitions it relies upon. If they are not acceptable
or not accepted by those the demonstration is intended to persuade, it is
useless. If the intended 'audience' of the demonstration and of the definitions
is the author himself, he can of course declare his satisfaction. But how much
weight does a demonstration that satisfies only its author add to the reasons
he must be conscious of in order to believe its conclusion? In such a case, the
suspicion may rightly arise that, having first adopted (by virtue of other
reasons) the belief in the conclusion, the author crafts definitions that
'demonstrate' it. But if this is the case, the 'demonstration' can hardly
function as an independent reason for the author's belief and its only viable
function is to persuade someone else—in which case, if the addressee does not
accept the definitions, it cannot fulfill its purpose.
Demonstrations in
this respect are "situated", especially when used as arguments in a
dialectical context where an explicit or implicit opponent is expected to
fulfill the critical duties of his or her dialectical role by raising
objections. In the case of the thesis 'proved' in "On the obligation to
believe", Leibniz's allusion to possible opponents is not gratuitous. He
knows quite well who they are: the Catholics who, since they do not accept the
Lutheran conclusion, are likely to use their scholastic abilities to undermine
the definitions Leibniz uses, and thus the weight of the 'demonstration'
allegedly proving it. The proponent of a demonstration, as of any other
argument in such a situation, cannot forget that his primary task is persuading
an audience, by providing reasons acceptable to the audience and in this way
leading it to espouse the beliefs the proponent is interested in promoting.
Formal validity alone won't do. Nor the appeal to recta ratio per se will be sufficient, unless the concepts, the
principles, the authoritative sources, the procedures of interpretation, and
even the set of valid arguments are those the audience is able and willing to
accept.
In the complex
dialectic situation underlying the demonstration-like arguments of the Examination, where the implicitly
self-appointed, participant-observer mediator has to propose positions
tolerable to the two disputing parties—with special attention to one of them
(the Church of Rome) which is the primary intended addressee—Leibniz has to
perform a skillful tightrope act. And his performance is indeed admirable,
beginning with the opening announcement of an impartial use of uncorrupted
reason. Nevertheless, the traces of what Albert de Broglie, a 19th
century translator of the Examination,
has called Leibniz's "subtle dialectics" (in P. Lacroix, ed., Système Religieux de Leibniz,
Paris, 1846, p. xi), are not difficult to detect.
To begin with, the
workings of the recta ratio must be
"confirmed"—a word aptly chosen by the Introduction (p. lxxviii)—by
ecclesiastic tradition, i.e., by the faithful transmission of the opinions and
decisions of the "pious antiquity". This vague expression refers to a
pool of 'ancient' Christian authorities, naturally pre-Reformation and
therefore usually accepted by both Protestants and Catholics. Given the enormous weight of the reliance on
"authorities" in theological argumentation, the choice of the most
favorable set of them is extremely important, since bringing up the appropriate
authoritative opinion is often the decisive move—unless, of course, there are
even weightier arguments. For instance, regarding the hotly disputed question
of transubstantiation, "if it were possible to demonstrate by irrefutable
arguments of metaphysical necessity that the essence of bodies consists in
extension", then "one would have to admit that, even through divine
intervention, a body cannot be in several places [at once], just as the
diagonal cannot be commensurable with the sides of a square" (p. 2420).
Were such a demonstration available, one would have to interpret Christ's words
"This is my body" allegorically (ibid.). Yet those philosophers that
purported to provide such a demonstration failed clamorously (a clear allusion
to Descartes' "memorable error") and it is unlikely any demonstration
of this sort is forthcoming. So, the literal interpretation prevails on the
strength of the fact that "pious antiquity has openly declared many times
that the bread is transmuted into the body of Christ and the wine in his
blood", i.e., that transubstantiation actually does takes place (ibid.).
If the voice of "pious antiquity" is not unanimous or is liable to
different interpretations—and we have seen (5.2) that this is not unusual—then
each party, as well as the "mediator", can pick out those 'ancient'
opinions that most fit its needs at each step of the argumentation. Leibniz's
incredible erudition in Church history and canonical law—he was able to refer
to precedents or councils nobody seems to remember—is of great help in allowing
his recta ratio to operate
efficiently under the vigilant eye of a "pious antiquity" not quite
innocently interpreted by his partisan contemporaries, among whom he himself
must be ranged. To be sure, the best rule in all these matters, as he writes
after discussing the issue of divorce, is "to follow the Church's judgment
and to acknowledge its power" (p. 2448), but there are different ways of
interpreting what precisely that judgment is and how to follow it.
The more recent and
therefore more controversial sources, especially the Council of Trent, cannot
be neglected, but the rope in this case is so tight that one wonders how
Leibniz nevertheless managed to walk it. The Protestants' denial of the
ecumenical legitimacy of the council because they were not admitted to it, and
Rome's intransigence in considering the acceptance of its decisions as a sine
qua non for their re-admission into the Church seem to preclude any possible
compromise. Under these conditions the best argumentative strategy would be to
refer to the contentious Council of Trent as little as possible. Leibniz,
however, does not avoid altogether such references.
He concludes his
discussion on the issue of divorce, for instance, by quoting a passage of the
council's decision endorsing the most rigorous prohibition of divorce under any
circumstances and condemning as anathema any criticism of this decision as being
a mistake. But, in a subtle pragmatic move, he goes on to discern in this very
strong statement signs of "some moderation", since it does not
condemn those who have thought (and
acted) otherwise, but only those who have said
the Church was wrong in adopting the doctrine it did. The latter, he admits, is
indeed an example of obstinacy (which amounts to contesting the doctrine of the
infallibility of the Church) that deserves to be anathematized. Furthermore—he
adds—these obstinate critics forget that, in practice, when it comes to the
enforcement of the decision, it is in the power of the Church to be indulgent
and to mitigate its doctrinal stance whenever there are "mighty
reasons" (maximas rationes)
against its implementation—a power the Church has actually exercised in certain
cases (p. 2147). The innuendo is obvious: were the Catholic moderation matched
by a similar Protestant moderation, this and similar contentious issues might
be resolved. Needless to say, this typical mediating move, which the 'moderate
bishops' he intended to first submit the Examination
to might perhaps accept as 'tolerable', was far from being viewed as such by
defenders of a strict adherence to orthodoxy, on the Catholic side, and
partisans of direct confrontation with such an orthodoxy, on the Protestant
side. The already mentioned translator of the Examination, for example, adds a note to this passage, in this
spirit, adverting that "the Church in no way arrogates for itself the
power that Leibniz so generously attributes to it of permitting polygamy and
divorce in cases of absolute necessity" (in Lacroix, op. cit., p. 383).
Another interesting
example of Leibniz's subtle 'mitigated acceptance' strategy vis-à-vis
Trent authority is his use of extensive extracts of the council's resolution on
the cult of images, on the grounds that their verbatim quotation is "the
surest way to correctly learn what this cult consists in" (p.
2395)—notwithstanding the fact that the council's description of this practice
may be seen by those who criticize this cult as rather tendentious, since the
decision is to preserve, rather than to eliminate it. Leibniz goes a step
further, by not only suggesting
(through the approval of the council's description) that the decision is
reasonable, but also by asserting
that it is: "I don't see what can be reprehensible in these words of the
council", especially since the council explicitly adds that "if
abuses have crept into this practice the council vehemently wishes them to be
extirpated" (ibid.).
The topics of images
and their cult occupy about twenty of the hundred pages of the Examination. A wide variety of pro and
con arguments—historical, anthropological, psychological, sociological,
theological, and semiotic—are employed. I want to single out the latter, due to
its relevance to Leibniz's conclusion. From a semiotic point of view, Leibniz
stresses, nothing is clearer than the distinction the council uses between a
sign and what it signifies, whose application to the case at hand he nevertheless
undertakes to further clarify (p. 2396). He also relies upon his semiotic views
and experience (manifest in both the Discourse
on Metaphysics and the General
Inquiries) for supporting the council's claim that images are efficient to
induce in believers states of mind that contribute to their piety. In fact,
according to Leibniz signs are necessary for our mental and spiritual life,
since we are not pure spirits. "If it is possible for us to form internal
ideas of things that do not fall under the senses, we cannot however either
fixate upon them our attention or engrave them in our mind without adjoining to
them certain external signs—words, characters, representations, analogies,
examples […]; furthermore, the more efficient signs are those that are more
significant (significantiores),
representing more properties of the thing represented, especially if the signs
are in themselves striking and attractive" (p. 2387)—an interesting
extension of the "law of expression" (see 6.5). To this brief summary
of his semiotics he might have added what is perhaps its central point, namely
that signs, which are indispensable for the fixation and recall of abstract
ideas, are also essential for thought and reasoning—that is, that they are in
fact constitutively involved in mental processes.
Why is all this
relevant to the conclusion, in which Leibniz reiterates that, "everything
considered", the council's decision to preserve "the veneration of
the original through the image (which is what the cult of images consists in)
is wise and pious, provided it is kept, with extreme precautions, within its
limits" (pp. 2399-2400)? If indeed the real point of contention, as
suggested above, consists in the abuses of the cult (one of them illustrated in
a story Leibniz tells immediately after his conclusion), then the additional
precautions in Leibniz's proviso should definitely satisfy the Protestants. It
is in fact Leibniz's emphasis on these precautions that embodies his
"mitigated acceptance" strategy in this particular case. If the
Protestants still resisted, maybe it was not only because they saw in the cult
of images as such a flagrant
violation of the Law of God as delivered to Moses, but also because they were
perhaps aware of Leibniz's semiotics and suspected that, if sign and signified
are so close and enmeshed in the workings of a logician's or mathematician's
mind, in the mind of ordinary persons—the practitioners of the cult of
images—it might well be impossible to disentangle them.
Let me try now to
disentangle the conclusions that follow from what has been said in this
section. That there is an underlying dialectical structure governing the
argumentation in the Examination and
that it is clearly and heavily situated should by now be apparent. That the
specifics of this structure—two contenders asymmetrically addressed by an
observer-judge-participant-mediator—impose specific requirements and
constraints should also be apparent. In particular it imposes a deliberative
mode of proceeding, manifested in a constant flip flop marked by concessive
conjunctions (but, although, etc.) and locutions such as on the one hand …on the other hand. This
mode evokes the scales image, and implies that the most one can expect from the
conclusions is that the sum of the arguments supporting them inclines but does not necessitate, so that their force and
eventual contribution to the ultimate objective—reunification—lies in their
ability to persuade the contenders,
not to compel them by the sheer force
of 'radical reason'. The mediator's presence and active participation in
re-interpreting the positions of the adversaries and formulating reconciling
alternatives—as the 'judge of
controversies' envisaged by Leibniz (e.g., in "On controversies", a
text of 1680 not included in VI.4, but in IV.3) is expected to do—modifies the
rules of the dialectical game. Instead of a dispute where the objective is to win, it becomes a negotiation, where the
objective is to win over the
adversaries to a common ground 'tolerable' to both, whence a reasonable resolution
of the conflict can be found.
The specificity of
the Examination can be seen if we
compare it with the Consideratio on
the one hand and the Positiones, on
the other. While the former can be viewed as a discussion of one of the many
issues the Examination deals with and
as employing a similar flip flop, dialectically-based mode of deliberative
argumentation, as a model for resolving controversies it lacks: (a) the
comprehensive coverage and systematic structure that would permit to see where
a specific issue it deals with fits in and what is its contribution to the
whole controversy, and (b) the freedom to muster potentially relevant arguments
of all kinds, rather than only those narrowly defined as relevant (in this
case, those based on the authority of authoritative sources) by the 'localized'
nature of the debated issue. The Positiones,
on the other hand, strips the arguments and conclusions from their dialectical
clothing and presents them in the minimalist nudity of a strict
definition-demonstration sequence; by thereby suppressing their situated
nature, they may gain in conciseness and clarity but are likely to loose in the
ability to persuade the real participants in the drama. It seems to me that
what is peculiar in the Examination
is that it somehow succeeds in combining the virtues of the two texts mentioned
while avoiding their vices. Maybe its main achievement lies in providing, in
this way, an intermediary and perhaps more effective model for handling complex
controversies.
6.7 Division of labor
If one acknowledges and puts
together the 'radical' and 'softer' reason pictures, rather than seeing them as
competing, a compound 'big picture' emerges, where apparently disparate
endeavors of Leibniz can be seen as occupying their proper place in the puzzle.
If we look at the three 1686 texts we have examined in this way, we can
conceptualize their respective contributions to the big picture, as well as
their inter-relations, in terms of a 'division of labor'.
Indeed,
in 1686 Leibniz's rationalism crystallizes into a system where "two great
principles" divide between themselves ontology as well as epistemology
into separate areas of jurisdiction—the principle of contradiction ruling over
necessary truths, the principle of perfection or sufficient reason over
contingent truths. Although the notion of truth itself is the same in both
domains, knowing these truths requires different epistemic means. Since the
"inclining" means needed for the knowledge of contingent truths
cannot be reduced to the "formal" means needed for the knowledge of
necessary truths, a split in 'reason' seems thus to be implied. But the split
is only apparent if one foregoes the picture that identifies reason with the
latter and views both as different but complementary components, necessary for
reason to fulfill its encompassing job of accounting for rationality in every
domain: the possible as well as the actual, the theoretical as well as the
practical, the divine as well as the human. Given the complexity of this job
for us humans, the split it seems to imply is nothing but a division of labor.
From
this perspective, it is clear that the General
Inquiries is concerned with the realm of the possible, i.e., with all that
can be accounted for in terms of one of the two great principles alone. It
"inquires" about the foundations of this realm, develops the tools
for discovering its truths, and explores the limits of such tools. The Discourse on Metaphysics, in its turn,
is mainly concerned with the realm of the actual, i.e., with that whose
rationality depends, in addition, from the other great principle. It focuses on
the foundations of this domain, on the general characteristics of the epistemic
tools it requires, and gives some examples of them, drawn mainly from the field
of physics. But the Discourse does
not pause to develop such tools in detail and systematically. This task is left
for the 'new logic' that will comprise, in addition to the calculative means
developed by the General Inquiries,
the softer means characteristic of the knowledge of the contingent. In his past
work as well as in the work of others, Leibniz is able to pick out
"examples" (specimina) of
these tools. But, although the task
is clearly delineated by Leibniz in the following decades, its magnitude is
such that its fulfillment remains—as in most of his other projects—only
fragmentarily dealt with.
But
life does not stop. Contingency presses. Praxis
cannot wait for researchers to develop the theory and design the tools. In
particular, religious controversies must be rationally handled before they lead
to further devastating wars. The 'new logic' must be applied even before it
exists as a corpus of doctrine and practical methods. The Examination comes to fill this gap. In so doing, it reveals how
little one should rely on the dichotomy theory vs. practice. For, once involved
in participating in an actual controversy, one has to find out by experience,
as it were 'intuitively', the most efficient strategy to adopt as well as the
most efficient tactic to follow at each step. One must learn, for instance,
that "there is one truth, but not everything is easy and intelligible by
everybody". This is a quote from the Introduction (p. lxxiii; see also
5.2), which I interpret—as might be expected by now—in my own way, as meaning
that, in the practice of controversy one soon learns that the persuading
argument is not necessarily the one that expresses luminously or demonstrates
the "one truth", but rather the one that skillfully argues "from
the point of view of the adversary", taking into account not only what is
intelligible to him but also what is possible for him to accept, given the
circumstances. One learns that for an appeal to the recta ratio to be effective, it must take into account not only
universal principles of rationality, but how the opponent concretely interprets
such principles in a given context (i.e., one must ask why is it that what I
consider to be contradictory is not necessarily so for my opponent). These
lessons were not forgotten by the Leibniz of the Nouveaux Essais and the Théodicée.
They should also be kept in mind by the theoreticians and developers to come of
the 'new logic', because they suggest it should include significant chunks of
rhetorical principles and methods—something the 'old logic' would certainly
abhor.
If
we were to order the three texts considered in the present section on a scale
of context-bound or 'situated' vs. context-free or 'ethereal', the Examination is certainly the most
situated of them, the General Inquiries
the most ethereal, and the Discourse on
Metaphysics should be located fairly close to the latter. I submit that the
breakthrough of 1686 does not consist in each of these texts' achievements per
se, significant as they certainly are. It rather consists in the fact that,
mostly implicitly but sometimes explicitly, they interact, both by borrowing
from each other whenever appropriate and—even more significantly—by revealing
each other's limitations. What more could one expect from a successful division
of labor?
7. Impact
It is time now to wind up with
some speculation. Every edition of Leibniz's works which increased the public's
access to the unpublished trove well kept in the Leibniz Archive in
In this respect, the
present collection differs significantly from the two previous 20th
century editions of unpublished manuscripts that had such a major
impact—Couturat's Opuscules et fragments
inédits (1903) and Grua's Textes
inédits (1948). Whereas both of these editions did not purport to be
in any way comprehensive, chronologically or thematically, volume VI.4 purports
in fact to be thematically exhaustive for a given chronological period.
Therefore, whereas both Couturat and Grua could be unabashedly selective,
VI.4's inevitable selectivity can only marginally affect the picture or
pictures that emerge from the volume. Both Couturat and Grua indeed selected
the texts they were to publish in the light of their comprehensive
interpretations of some aspect of Leibniz's philosophy, which they had developed
on the basis of those texts—interpretations made public in their books on,
respectively, logic (1901) and jurisprudence (1953). One can say that an
edition informed by an interpretation naturally bears its heavy imprint and
highlights the pattern or picture the editor has discerned in the chosen
collection of texts. The editors of VI.4, and especially Heinrich Schepers,
also had in their minds an interpretation and pattern, clearly expressed in the
Introduction, and marginally in the thematic organization and a few decisions
about the inclusion of certain groups of texts. But the imprint of Schepers'
interpretation upon the ensemble of texts offered to the reader is much weaker
than in the case of Grua and Couturat. This is extremely important, as this review
tried to substantiate, because it makes it easier for the reader to discern in
the collection patterns other than those the editors have seen.
Let
me now turn to further aspects of VI.4's eventual impact. First, from the point
of view of an internal-structural historiography, the appearance under the same
cover of such an ensemble of texts necessarily yields a better understanding of
the connections, often subtle or altogether hidden, between the various strands
of Leibniz's mature thought—the commercium
between its plural aspects and parts he often advertises as characteristic of
his 'system'. In the tracing of these connections, the Subject Index is of
extraordinary help. We should remember, regarding this point, that for Leibniz
words have a constitutive role in thought, so that they are a precious guide if
we wish "inside information" on thinking in general (see 6.5) and on
the workings of his thinking in particular. The many erased and modified
variants of a text that appear at the bottom of each page, as well as the
appearance, spreading and dominance of new terms and locutions in his
vocabulary (which can be followed in the index), are examples of how VI.4 can
provide this sort of insight.
From
the point of view of a broader, context-oriented historiography, VI.4 in fact
also provides a detailed panorama of Leibniz's philosophy in the context of his
time. This philosophy emerges as a multi-faceted alternative to the towering
thought of Descartes and its offshoot, the Cartesianism Leibniz considered to
be an unfit sequel to the master's genius. The many pieces in which he
criticizes Descartes and the Cartesians reveal how much his own thought was
shaped in a contrastive way. An equally formative role is discernible in his
careful study and discussion of Spinoza, Malebranche, Arnauld, Hobbes (and,
later, Locke and Bayle), as well as of lesser figures, with most of whom he
held actual debates. In fact, the decision to include in each of the six
thematic divisions of the volume abundant evidence of his attentive critical
readings is a blessing in this respect.Readers
are encouraged not to overlook these pieces, for they are essential for
understanding the positions this deeply dialogical-dialectical thinker adopts.
Had more of his controversy writings—especially in theology—been included, this
characteristic would have become even more salient. But in what is included
there is enough to highlight not only Leibniz's modus operandi, but also to what extent intellectual production in
the République des Lettres was
at the time substantially based on swift communication, debate and criticism.
The impact of a
volume such as this must also be considered from the point of view of a
'historiography of the future'. Leibniz's legacy contains endless new ideas, some
of which are half-baked or difficult to understand, as well as insights, hints,
suggestions and plans—all of which amount to as many tasks for us to perform:
interpreting, comparing, reconstructing, criticizing, and eventually developing
and applying. Virtually all his projects remained uncompleted, part of them due
to their intrinsic open-ended nature, which mirrors his historical-dynamic
conception of human knowledge. I happen to believe in a "user's"
rather than an "observer's" approach to the history of ideas. For me
the history of ideas is not only a repository of past thoughts to be preserved,
displayed and admired as if in a museum.
It is also a source of insights that can be put to use and developed
with a view to solving the problems—theoretical as well as practical—one's own
era faces. This is especially important in the case of an imaginative thinker
such as Leibniz, who preserved so much of his thought "for us", his
posterity.
In
previous generations, a philosopher of the stature of Frege attempted to
realize with his Begriffschrift what
he understood to be the gist of one of Leibniz's most cherished projects, the
Universal Characteristic. A century later, a different picture of Leibniz's
rationalism—wherein Frege's interpretation (shared by many other 20th
century philosophers and Leibniz scholars) is but a part of a bigger puzzle—begins
to emerge. The 'new logic' this broader and softer conception of rationality
implies was sketched out by Leibniz but remains to be developed. Other patterns
that the careful reading of this volume may reveal to other eyes surely will
also imply unfinished tasks to be performed. Thanks to the editors of volume
VI.4, we have now in our hands an invaluable additional part of a still
incompletely edited philosophical legacy that permits us—indeed, requires us,
as Leibniz's heirs—to continue to explore the patterns it contains and make use
of the insights they reveal. It is up to us, and to future generations, to pick
up this challenge!