Some Aspects of Cognitive Poetics
Aspects of Cognitive Poetics
This chapter purports to be a short introduction to
Cognitive Poetics.1
After a short introductory section,
it will present some aspects of Cognitive Poetics,
focussed on a few brief case studies.
When one considers
the perceived qualities of poetry, one cannot escape
facing a rather disconcerting issue. Words designate
"compact" concepts, whereas some poetry at
least is said to evoke diffuse emotions, vague moods,
or varieties of mystic experiences. Furthermore, as
brain-research of the last few decades seems to suggest,
language is a predominantly sequential activity, of
a conspicuously logical character, typically associated
with the left cerebral hemisphere; whereas diffuse
emotional processes are typically associated with the
right cerebral hemisphere. Thus, while we can name
emotions, language does not appear to be well suited
to convey their unique diffuse character. Accordingly,
emotional poetry, or mystic poetry ought to be a contradiction
in terms. We know that this is not the case. But this
presentation of the problem emphasises that we have
all too easily accepted what ought not to be taken
for granted. The major part of this paper will discuss
some ways poetry has found to escape, in the linguistic
medium, from the tyranny of clear-cut conceptual categories.
The case studies to be presented will illustrate how
emotional qualities can be conveyed by poetry; and,
as a more extreme instance, how "altered states
of consciousness" are displayed by strings of
words. One of the key-words in this respect is "precategorial
information"; or, perhaps, "verbal imitation
of precategorial information". Two additional
key-words will be "thing-free" and "gestalt-free".
Psychologists distinguish "rapid" and "delayed
categorisation". "Precategorial information"
is more accessible through the latter. It will be pointed
out that the reader's decision style may be decisive
here. Persons who are intolerant of uncertainty or
ambiguity may seek rapid categorisation and miss some
of the most crucial aesthetic qualities in poetry,
including emotional as well as grotesque qualities.
During the past fifty years or so, the word cognition
has changed its meaning. Originally, it distinguished
the rational from the emotional and impulsive aspect
of mental life. Now it is used to refer to all information-processing
activities of the brain, ranging from the analysis
of immediate stimuli to the organisation of subjective
experience. In contemporary terminology, cognition
includes such processes and phenomena as perception,
memory, attention, problem-solving, language, thinking,
and imagery. In the phrase Cognitive Poetics, the term
is used in the latter sense.
For my purpose, the term "poetics" may be defined as follows:
The actual objects of poetics are the particular regularities that occur in literary texts and that determine the specific effects of poetry; in the final analysis--the human ability to produce poetic structures and understand their effect--that is, something which one might call poetic competence (Bierwisch, 1970: 98-99).
Cognitive Poetics comes in precisely here: it offers
cognitive hypotheses to relate in a systematic way
"the specific effects of poetry" to "the
particular regularities that occur in literary texts".
I shall illustrate this in a moment, with relation
to a Hebrew and an English text. But first let us proceed
by mentioning a few central assumptions of Cognitive
Poetics.
One major assumption of cognitive poetics is that poetry
exploits, for aesthetic purposes, cognitive (including
linguistic) processes that were initially evolved for
non-aesthetic purposes, just as in evolving linguistic
ability, old cognitive and physiological mechanisms
were turned to new ends. Such an assumption is more
parsimonious than postulating independent aesthetic
and/or linguistic mechanisms. The reading of poetry
involves the modification (or, sometimes, the deformation)
of cognitive processes, and their adaptation for purposes
for which they were not originally "devised".
In certain extreme but central cases, this modification
may become "organised violence against cognitive
processes", to paraphrase the famous slogan of
Russian Formalism. Quite a few (but by no means all)
central poetic effects are the result of some drastic
interference with, or at least delay of, the regular
course of cognitive processes, and the exploitation
of its effects for aesthetic purposes. In this respect,
one should point out that emotions are efficient orientation
devices; and that much manneristic poetry is, precisely,
poetry of disorientation. The cognitive correlates
of poetic processes must be described, then, in three
respects: the normal cognitive processes; some kind
of modification or disturbance of these processes;
and their reorganisation according to different principles.
Cognitive Poetics may be interested in two complementary issues regarding the creativity and novelty manifested in poetic language. 1: Given that this creative use of language results in the intricacies and complexities of poetic language, what are the unique cognitive processes which this complex use of language requires. 2. Given the fact that despite its complexity, poetic language is, in principle, interpretable, what are the general (i.e., non-specific to the poetic use of language) cognitive constraints, the adherence to which, guarantees the interpretability of poetic language.
Poetry and Emotional Qualities
In the first paragraph of this paper I claimed that
language is a highly differentiated logical tool by
its very nature, and that it requires special manipulations
to convey or evoke with its help low-differentiated,
diffuse emotional qualities. Cognitive Poetics investigates
a variety of ways in which poets overcome this problem.
One efficient means for this investigation is to apply
to poetry knowledge gained by psychologists concerning
the nature of emotions (cf. Tsur, 1978). Psychologists
have discerned the following elements in emotions:
1. Cognitive situation appraisal ("cognitive", in the first sense);
2. Deviation from normal energy level: increase (gladness, anger), or decrease of energy (sadness, depression, calm);
3. Diffuse information in a highly activated state that is less differentiated than conceptual information;
4. Such information is active in "the back of one's mind", without pre-empting everything else.
Let us consider the first stanza of a short lyric poem by the great Hebrew poet Hayim Lensky (who wrote Hebrew poetry in Soviet Russia, and found his death in Stalin's concentration camps):
(1) The day is setting over the lake,
The fish have gone down to sleep in the depth,
Birds have ceased from their chatter...
How sad is the rustling of the reeds!
We may make two preliminary observations about this
stanza. First, it is only in the fourth line that it
names an emotion ("sad"); in the first three
lines it describes facts of the landscape that have
no explicit emotional contents. In other words, the
emotion appears to be there only by way of "telling",
not "showing". Intuitively, however, this
is not true, and we should attempt to account for this
intuition in a systematic way. Second, the four descriptive
sentences in the four lines relate to one another in
two different ways: in one way, they refer to parts
of the situation, complete one another to constitute
the description of a whole landscape; in another way,
they parallel one another in an important sense. The
latter relationship is reinforced by the rhyme pattern.
The reader is inclined to extract from parallel entities
their common ingredients. When the first three lines
are read out to students, they abstract from these
lines such abstractions as "going down",
"decrease of activity". When asked whether
this description has any emotional quality, they more
often than not suggest the emotional quality "calm".
We may recall that emotions are typically associated
with some deviation from normal energy level, and that
the lowering of energy is typically associated with
sadness, depression, or calm. It is only the fourth
line that supplies the "cognitive situation appraisal",
and resolves the emotional quality of the landscape
description in favour of "sadness".
There is convincing experimental evidence that the superordinate
categories of parallel entities is present, simultaneously
though subliminally, in active memory. This can be
demonstrated with the help of the Stroop test. The
Stroop test has revealed an involuntary and subliminal
cognitive mechanism of some interest for our present
inquiry. In this test, colour names (e.g., "yellow")
are written in different-coloured ink (e.g., "blue").
If the subject is required to read the word, he has
little interference from the ink colour, but if he
is required to name the ink colour, he has great difficulty
because of interference from the colour name (Posner,
1973: 26). The findings of this experiment suggested
a further study, concerning the automatic activation
of superordinates. In this study, subjects were presented
with lists of three words which they were to remember.
The three words came from the same category (e.g.,
"maple, "oak", "elm"). The
subjects were then shown one of the words in the list
(e.g., "oak"), the name of the category (e.g.,
"tree"), or a neutral word unrelated to the
list. These visually presented words were written in
coloured ink. The subjects were asked to name the colour
of the ink as rapidly as possible. Based on the Stroop
effect, it was expected that if the word shown to the
subject was in activated memory, the subjects would
have greater trouble inhibiting a tendency to vocalise
the word name. Such a tendency would slow their response
to naming the ink colour. The experimental data showed
that words from the list ("maple, "oak",
"elm") and the category name ("tree")
produced greater interference with colour naming than
control words. This study suggests that the category
name is activated when a list word is presented, without
any requirement to do so (Posner, 1973: 86). One might
perhaps cautiously suggest that the same principle
may be extended to ad hoc categories too: that when
the first three lines of Lensky's poem are read, the
superordinate categories "going down", "decrease
of activity" are activated too. Such an assumption,
however, requires further experimental testing.
The abstractions extracted from parallel entities have
considerable adaptation value. As Posner suggested,
such abstractions may contribute to a parsimonious
hierarchical organisation of semantic memory. One might
add that they also facilitate the preservation of such
parallel entities in active memory. As suggested above,
one major assumption of cognitive poetics is that poetry
exploits, for aesthetic purposes, cognitive processes
that were initially evolved for non-aesthetic purposes.
In the present instance, the abstractions that typically
serve to alleviate the load on active memory (or contribute
to the efficient organisation of semantic memory) receive
exceptionally strong emphasis and are perceived as
aspects of the emotional quality pervading the landscape
described. As aspects of the emotional quality pervading
the landscape described, such abstractions conform
with the description of emotions above: they constitute
diffuse information in a highly activated state that
is less differentiated than conceptual information,
and are active in "the back of one's mind",
without pre-empting everything else. This is how this
stanza evokes some diffuse emotion or vague mood. But
these are attributed to the physical behaviour of animals
and lifeless physical reality, not to human emotions.
This, however, seems to bother very few--if any--poetry
readers. They all seem to have acquired the basic convention
of "literary competence", formulated by Jonathan
Culler as the rule of significance: "read the
poem as expressing a significant attitude to some problem
concerning man and/or his relation to the universe"
(Culler, 1975: 115).
The right side of the cortex processes its input more as a "patterned whole", that is, in a more simultaneous manner than does the left. This simultaneous processing is advantageous for the integration of diffuse inputs, such as for orienting oneself in space, when motor, kinesthetic and visual input must be quickly integrated. This mode of information-processing, too, would seem to underlie an "intuitive" rather than "intellectual" integration of complex entities (Ornstein, 1975: 95).
In what I shall call below "delayed categorisation",
the phrase "integration of diffuse inputs"
undergoes a slight shift of emphasis, from "integration
of diffuse inputs" to "integration of diffuse
inputs". In the reading of landscape descriptions
by way of "delayed categorisation", inputs
are perceived as more diffuse.
(2) A widow bird sate mourning for her love
Upon a wintry bough;
The frozen wind crept on above,
The freezing stream below.There was no leaf upon the forest bare,
No flower upon the ground,
And little motion in the air
Except the mill-wheel's sound.
The first thing that one notices in this short lyric
is its exquisite musicality. The second thing that
one notices is its intense emotional quality, its intense
atmosphere. Yet, except for the first line, all the
poem gives us merely a catalogue of physical facts,
of what there is, or is not in the concrete reality
presented. There are three barely noticeable, interrelated
metaphors in the first line, if we assume that only
human beings may have loves and become widows when
they die, and mourn for them. However, the attribution
of these notions to a bird is not very bold. The only
other formal metaphor in the poem is crept on, in the
sense of "moved on slowly"; this is not a
very bold metaphor either. The rest of the poem contains
plain, non-metaphorical language. By what means does,
then, the poem generate the intense emotional atmosphere?
Hardly by these metaphors alone.
There is contiguity between the bird and the bough upon
which it is sitting; and there is contiguity between
the bough and the tree, of which presumably it is a
part. Furthermore, there is contiguity between the
tree, the wind, the stream, the forest, the ground,
and the mill-wheel's sound: they all combine to a coherent
landscape. In other words, all these items are parts,
"metonymies", of the whole scene. However,
the poem also projects the principle of equivalence
from the axis of similarity to the axis of contiguity:
lines three and four are similar in that both the stream
and the wind have low temperature (are freezing, or
frozen), and that both are "creeping on".
Likewise, lines five and six are similar in that they
both describe the absence of vegetation that has vitality
(flower or leaf). Now how does all this affect the
abstract emotional quality of the poem? One important
ingredient in emotions involves deviation from the
normal level of energy. Joy, mirth or, for that matter,
anger, consist in heightened psychic energy, whereas
calm, sorrow or depression consist in a lowered level
of energy. Thus, emotions also involve a lowered or
heightened level of vitality.
However, whatever the energy levels mentioned in the
landscape description, they do not concern human emotions,
but only lifeless or growing things. There is a lowering
of energy when the wind and the stream are freezing
or frozen (in the cold ~ hot opposition, cold designates
the low-energy pole, hot the high-energy pole); and
slowness is implied by the verb crept instead of moved.
There appears to be some analogy between the bird which
sate upon the wintry bough, and the wind and the stream:
all of them manifest some drastically reduced activity.
Now the reduced activity of the wind and the stream
could also suggest calm, for instance. It is the widow
bird which "sate mourning for her love",
that gives the emotional direction of distress to the
reduced activity of physical reality. Lines five and
six contribute the components [+deprivation] and [vitality]
to this emotional quality. Now consider the techniques
for introducing "overtones of human emotion"
into this poem. The song both stresses "the great
likeness between man and nature in terms of sympathies
and feeling", and lays an "emphasis on qualitative
comparison between objects in terms of sense perception".
The former technique consists in the analogy between
the bird (rather than some human being) and its environment;
the latter in the analogies between the pairs of items
present or absent in the landscape. But both are instances
of the principle formulated by Roman Jakobson (1960) as The
poetic function projects the principle of equivalence
from the axis of selection to the axis of combination.
Thus, the emotional quality is present in the poem not only by way of telling but also by way of showing. It should also be noticed that this emotional quality being spread over the whole scenery, the information is perceived as diffuse, very much in the way information is held in a diffuse state in affects and emotions. It is precisely this that turns the notion of an emotion into an emotional quality; or, in other words, into an emotional atmosphere. It is in this way that atmosphere in the sense of "the gaseous fluid surrounding the earth" becomes a metaphor for an emotional quality pervading a work of art: the air is felt to be everywhere, yet cannot be perceived by any of the senses. The last two lines of the poem have, then, a rather complex function within the whole. Little as a part of the sequence There is no ... No... And little... suggests "none at all"; in this sense, "And little motion in the air" is one more item in the list of analogous items suggesting deprivation. In this sense, it seems to herald an unqualified statement that generates a psychological atmosphere of great certainty. The subsequent preposition except, however, makes a substantial qualification to this statement, substituting "a very small amount of" for total exclusion; that is, there is an exclusion from the total exclusion: a mill-wheel's sound. The relation of the mill-wheel to its sound is like the relation of a thing to a thing-free quality. What seems to be emphasised by this is that only the thing-free quality, but not the thing itself is introduced into the description. This perturbation of the air becomes another item in the list of items with reduced activity; by the same token, it emphasises the presence of the air, the thing-free quality par excellence pervading the scene. This shift of the meaning, qualifying the unqualified statement, performs a "poetic sabotage" against the determined, purposeful quality of the poetic closure, replacing the psychological atmosphere of great certainty with a psychological atmosphere of uncertainty, contributing to the emotional quality of the poem. This emotional atmosphere has been generated by the abstraction of certain qualities from parallel concrete items in the description. This quality seems to be reinforced by another aspect of the mill-wheel's sound, which I wish to point out through an idea borrowed from Joseph Glicksohn. Gestalt psychology speaks of figure-ground relationship. The undifferentiated mill-wheel's sound typically serves as ground to some aural figure. By forcing to the reader's attention a percept that typically serves as ground, the poem increases the emotional quality of the perception, and emphasises that there is no figure to be contemplated, reinforcing the quality of deprivation.
Rapid and Delayed Categorisation
The shortest way to illustrate rapid and delayed categorisation
is the following story. As is well known, Helen Keller
was deaf, mute, and blind. She began to acquire the
basic skills of communication as late as at the age
of six. Before that age, she tells us in her book,
she had no word for, e.g., ice cream. When she felt
like eating ice cream, she felt an intense cold feeling
all over her tongue, and drew her mother to the fridge.
Later, after having acquired the word ice cream, the
peculiar sensation on her tongue disappeared, and she
was incapable of reviving it by conscious effort. 2
Most normal adults delay categorisation
for fractions of seconds, so as to gather information
required for making adequate judgments about reality.
This is a requirement for satisfactory adaptation.
In Helen Keller's case, categorisation was delayed
for over six years; and the story can demonstrate the
advantages and disadvantages of rapid and delayed categorisation.
A category with a verbal label constitutes relatively
small load on one's cognitive system, and is easily
manipulable; on the other hand, it entails the loss
of important sensory information, that might be crucial
for the process of accurate adaptation. Delayed categorisation,
by contrast, may load too much sensory load on the
human memory system; this overload may be available
for adaptive purposes and afford great flexibility,
but may be time-and-energy consuming, and occupy too
much mental processing space. Furthermore, delayed
categorisation may involve a period of uncertainty
that may be quite unpleasant, or even intolerable for
some individuals. Rapid categorisation, by contrast,
may involve the loss of vital information, and lead
to maladaptive strategies in life. In Helen Keller's
case, we see an opposition between a precategoric sensation
on her tongue, and a word. The former constitutes delayed,
the latter rapid categorisation. The diffuse sensations
are recoded into a compact, focussed concept, and labelled
with a verbal label. Different categorisation strategies
may generate different poetic qualities. Different
poetic texts may require different categorisation strategies.
In the instances considered shortly, the particular
poetic characteristics of poetic passages is missed,
if treated by way of rapid categorisation. This, however, is not necessarily always the case: we have found experimentally that the poetic potential
of, e.g., Omar Khayyam's Rubáiyáths may not
be fully realised by readers who are too tolerant of
delayed categorisation (cf. Tsur et al., 1990; 1991).
In what follows, I shall dwell on rapid and delayed
categorisation with reference to a variety of issues
related to poetry: understanding poetic metaphors,
the implied critic's decision style, and poetry and
altered states of consciousness.
Let us consider, first, an exquisite literary example. In an undergraduate seminar on Alterman's poetry, I isolated the following line from its context, and asked the students to make any comments that seemed relevant to them, without asking them any specific questions.
(3) From the village drowning in the moan of the oxen
The first responses received from the students represented
the view that one may not refer to an isolated line,
without relating it to its context. This is an academically
approved, well-proven strategy of avoiding the need
to experience evasive, "perceptual", poetic
qualities, that cannot be subsumed under some clearly-defined,
conceptual category. When I promised them that after
discussing the peculiar qualities of the isolated verse
line we shall examine it in its wider context, students
began making such remarks as that the words drowning
and moan have sinister connotations. This too is a
well-proven strategy, with full academic backing, to
avoid the direct experiencing of unevaluated and unclassified
stimuli. So I asked the students whether the image
really evoked unpleasant, or sinister feelings. The
students were surprised to discover that the image
was experienced as quite pleasant. The students had
troubles in answering my question, how can we explain
that a verse line in which two of the key terms have
sinister connotations arouses pleasurable feelings.
So I began a second round of disconcerting questions:
"What do we feel when taking a warm bath?"
Here it is more difficult to find academic legitimisation
for avoiding immediate sensations. The first answer
I received was "purification". This is an
excellent example of shifting the focus of discussion
from immediate, unevaluated--possibly nameless--sensations
to some stable concept with a venerable spiritual history.
The next answer was "wetness", which is tautological,
and quite uninformative. Both answers are perfectly
true, but involve a kind of "breaking the rules",
reserved for cases in which it is difficult to find
some respectable academic justification for evading
the need to face evasive, nameless sensory experiences.
Eventually, the following account began to emerge:
There is an undifferentiated, diffuse sensation all
over the outer surface of the skin, with an heightened
feeling of unity of the various parts of the body,
and a kind of harmony between the body and its immediate
environment, even an abolition of the separateness
of the body from its environment. This account was
found acceptable by most seminar members.
Returning now to Alterman's metaphor, the village is
perceived as if immersed in some gestalt-free and thing-free
entity, wrapping as it were the whole village or person,
enhancing the unity of the parts of the village (or
of the person), or transcending the split between the
person and his environment. There is here a kind of
regression of the perceiving consciousness from a state
of cognitive stability that discriminates between the
physical objects themselves, as well as between ego
and the physical objects perceived. Hence the pleasant
relaxation experienced through the metaphor, in spite
of the sinister connotations of several key terms in
it.
Consider now the noun moan. The Randomhouse College
Dictionary defines it as follows: "prolonged,
low, inarticulate sound uttered from or as from physical
or mental suffering". Such a definition has two
parts; one part gives a description of the sensory
information of "moan", the other suggests
its human significance and evaluation. Rapid categorisation
will concentrate only on its second part; delayed categorisation
will linger on its first, sensuous, part for as long
as possible, and proceed only later, if at all, to
its latter part. In Alterman's verse line, there is
a logical contradiction between the prepositional phrase
"in the moan of the oxen", and the verb suggesting
immersion in water. Drown and related verbs transfer
the transfer feature <+liquid> to their abstract
indirect objects. Sounds are perceived as thing-free
entities, that have no material mass. Consequently,
they cancel the material ingredient in the transfer
feature <+liquid>, and retain such ingredients
as "slight touch, diffuse and undifferentiated,
all over the outer surface of the body; the abolition
of the separateness of the body from its environment".
At the same time, the immersion of a solid body in
a thing-free entity arouses a feeling of condensation
of that wrapping entity (cf. Tsur, 1988b).
In a symposium on cognitive poetics (Tel Aviv University, 30.3.1993), I told the audience the story of this seminar session. One of the questions in the ensuing discussion concerned the "death" ingredient of drown. My answer referred to the feature-cancellation theory of metaphor: metaphoric contradiction deletes those features of the metaphoric term that are irrelevant to the frame, and foreground the relevant ones. Moan in Alterman's verse line foregrounds the peculiar sensuous quality of the oxen's lowing, and has nothing to do with "physical or mental suffering". Drowning suggests here immersion in this peculiar sensuous quality, and the death ingredient is irrelevant here. Such an analysis, however, ignores any possible differences between "the village drowning in the moan of the oxen", and "the village immersed in the moan of the oxen". A graduate student, member of the Cognitive Poetics workshop, suggested that the death ingredient may suggest here a state wherein individuality seems "to dissolve and fade away into boundless being"--to use the phrase of one of William James's informants; and, I think, this is the better answer.
Sensuous Metaphors and the Grotesque
Romantic poetry is a poetry of integration and orientation
that makes ample use of rich pre-categorial, or low-categorised
information. In the instances discussed in the preceding
section, an interference with the operation of the
orientation-mechanism was exploited for poetic effects.
This, however, is not necessarily the case in all poetry.
To show what I mean, let me begin with an extensive
discussion of two lines by the Hebrew poet Abraham
Shlonsky:
(4) A dead moon is hanging on nothingness
Like a white breast shedding its milk.
Let me begin, again, by reporting intuitions that some
of my students had about these lines. In a seminar
group, some of the students tended to interpret the
"breast shedding its milk" as the embodiment
of the principle of giving, of the life principle,
having a contradictory relationship to the moon as
"hung" and "dead" in the preceding
line. The moon is associated here, paradoxically, with
the principles of both life and death, with the principles
both of passivity and of "giving". Running
into difficulties, one of the students changed his
interpretation and said that "shedding its milk"
implies waste rather than feeding. All these interpretations,
however, were incompatible with the intuitions of other
participants in the seminar, including myself. Before
going into a possible other interpretation, it should
be noted that the above kind of interpretation is far
from illegitimate. It relies on one of the most important
principles of literary competence, formulated thus:
"The primary convention is what might be called
the rule of significance: read the poem as expressing
a significant attitude to some problem concerning man
and/or his relation to the universe" (Culler,
1975: 115). The interpretation is further corroborated
by one of the fundamental aesthetic principles, viz.,
that good poetry is paradoxical, that is, it consists
in the fusion of incompatible or discordant qualities.
The "rule of significance", peculiar as it
may seem from a literary point of view, is an operating
instruction realising, in the literary domain, a principle
that has much wider cultural applications. This principle
is formulated by D'Andrade (1980) as follows: "In
fusing fact and evaluational reactions, cultural schemata
come to have a powerful directive impact as implicit
values".
The above interpretation of Shlonsky's lines also relies
on "the convention of metaphorical coherence--that
one should attempt through semantic transformations
to produce coherence on both levels of tenor and vehicle"
(Culler, 1975: 115). There is an attempt to produce
coherence on the level of the tenor, associating the
moon with the principles of life and death, through
the appropriate semantic transformations. The level
of the vehicle, however, is "incoherent":
there is a "mixed metaphor" here. The moon
as hung and dead (like the head of a hanged man?) is
conflicting with the moon as a white breast. This line
of thought may lead us to an alternative way to handle
such metaphors. The first step in this direction goes
via Christine Brooke-Rose's work (1958). "Very
broadly speaking, metaphors can be divided, from the
point of view of idea-content, into functional metaphors
(A is called B by virtue of what it does), and sensuous
metaphors (A is called B by virtue of what it looks
like, or more rarely, sounds like, smells like, feels
like, tastes like)" (Brooke-Rose, 1958: 155).
Now, let us use Brooke-Rose's categories here to apply
explicit structural descriptions to the conflicting
intuitions. It is clear that the above interpretation
of Shlonsky's image treated it as a functional metaphor,
whereas in the emerging reading, "the moon [...] like a
white breast shedding its milk" is treated as
a conspicuous sensuous metaphor. Hence the conflicting
intuitions. The moon is called "a white breast
shedding its milk", not by virtue of its life-giving
activity, but by virtue of what it looks like: the
moon is a round object, near which a white mass, "the
Milky Way" is seen (pouring forth from it, as
it were). Now, why should a poet bother to provide
such rich imagery, if it were not to obtain some human
significance? For the precision of description, some
critics say. But the precision-explanation breaks down
when one considers the incompatible details that the
various images lump together. By contrast, one of the
major assumptions of cognitive poetics is able to explain
the conflict. Such sensuous metaphors as Shlonsky's
interfere with the normal process of orientation; the
conflict delays the appraisal of the human significance
of the image.
I have elsewhere claimed that a psychoanalytic discussion
of puns and caricatures may illuminate certain aspects
of figurative language (Tsur, 1987b: 19-32). 3 On first approximation, it seems obvious
that the image in (4) fuses two visual images into
one, while preserving their warring identity. The visual
conflict on the one hand, and the saving of mental
energy resulting from the fusion on the other hand,
generate the particular witty effect typically associated
with caricature. On a closer look, however, such an
explanation cannot account for the intuitive difference
between a "functional" and a "sensuous"
construal of the images involved. At most, we may say
that the saving of mental energy intensifies the reader's
involvement in whatever quality is generated by the
metaphor, whether construed as "functional"
or "sensuous".
More generally speaking, the urgency to evaluate the significance of a stimulus appears to be a deeply rooted biological response.
Most emotions involve an intuitive appraisal of a stimulus as good (beneficial) or bad (harmful). [...] It is very unlikely that organisms can unequivocally evaluate all stimuli with which they make contact. Some period, extended or brief, is necessary before tissue damage occurs, or internal injury develops, or pleasurable sensations occur. During this critical period of direct contact with an unevaluated object, a pattern of behavior apparently develops which, at the human level, is usually called surprise (Plutchik, 1968: 72).
Sensuous metaphor may, then, be regarded as another literary device to delay the smooth cognitive process consisting in the contact with some unevaluated image; the device's function is thus to prolong a state of disorientation and so generate an aesthetic quality of surprise, startling, perplexity, astounding, or the like. 4 Thus, Shlonsky's simile generates, under the pretence of precise description, a perceived effect of startling, or even emotional, disorientation. But the two lines contain additional devices of emotional disorientation, which will be discussed in the following. 5
The "sensuous" reader lingers at the visual
images, without appraising their significance. These
images, in spite of their common elements, are visually
incompatible. The moon, the female breast, and the
head of a dead person may be similar in their round
shapes, but they are different in many details. The
reader can join them visually only by the essentially
comic technique of caricature, thereby demonstrating
that the intolerable, inextricable mixture of incompatibles
is a fact of life, perhaps the most crucial one. No
wonder that such a reader perceives the image as grotesque,
in an essentially divided response, which conveys the
notion of something that is simultaneously laughable
and horrifying or disgusting. Both laughter and horror
or disgust are defence mechanisms in the presence of
threat, the latter allowing the danger its authority,
the former denying it (cf. Burke, 1957: 51-56). The
grotesque is the experiencing of emotional disorientation
when both defence mechanisms are suddenly suspended
(cf. Thomson, 1972: 58). Shlonsky's image contains
additional components of the grotesque. Some writers
on the grotesque claim that "the grotesque is
essentially physical, referring always to the body
and bodily excesses and celebrating these in an uninhibited,
outrageous but essentially joyous fashion" (Thomson,
1972: 56). "Our laughter at some kinds of the
grotesque and the opposite response--disgust, horror,
etc.--mixed with it, are both reactions to the physically
cruel, abnormal or obscene" (ibid., 8). There
is in the grotesque a kind of "delight in seeing
taboos flouted". The white breast of cosmic dimension
represents such an obscenity, or bodily excess.
The quotation from Shlonsky presents us with yet another
device of emotional disorientation, the 'realisation
of the idiom' "Milky Way" that is, the unexpected
use of the idiomatic expression in its literal sense.
Such sudden shifts of meaning may produce in the reader
"a strange sensation--making one suddenly doubt
one's comfortable relationship with language--not unlike
the sense of disorientation and confusion associated
with the grotesque" (Thomson, 1972: 65).
The grotesque, then, makes use of poetic devices that
produce an emotional disorientation which is experienced
as a shock, perplexity, surprise, or the like. It is,
indeed, this quality that enables the various devices
to combine and be integrated into a whole.
If one looks for an aesthetic justification of the above process, a sufficient answer will be: emotional disorientation is an intensive human quality perceived by the reader. One may justify one's positive evaluation of an aesthetic object with reference to three general canons: unity, complexity, and some intensive human quality (cf. Beardsley, 1958: 465-469). It is obvious from the above analysis that Shlonsky's two lines are quite complex from the viewpoint of figurative language. Insofar as this complexity is achieved by means of what Neo-Classical critics would call "mixed metaphors", these lines appear to be deficient from the point of view of unity. Notice, however, this: the various kinds of poetic devices, each in its own way, are aimed at giving a shock and arousing a sense of emotional disorientation. This generates an intense human quality of perplexity and emotional disorientation. This quality, in turn, bestows perceptual unity upon the diverse images. In this respect, the role of cognitive poetics is to describe the mechanisms of defence and orientation, the disturbance of which has generated the intense human quality. It also helps to define the nature of this quality and to relate it, systematically, to the poetic structures.
Decision Style
Our discussion of "Rapid and Delayed Categorisation",
and of "Sensuous Metaphors and the Grotesque"
may have suggested that readers may differ from one
another in their tolerance of delayed categorisation,
or of sensuous metaphors, or of the Grotesque. Such
differences in tolerance may affect their critical
decisions too. When confronted with a critical decision,
some readers or critics may prefer those options which
require less tolerance of delayed categorisation, or
of sensuous metaphors, or of the Grotesque; in short,
less tolerance of uncertainty or of emotional disorientation.
When in a piece of criticism, or in the output of a
critic, certain cognitive devices are consistently
deployed in a way that is characteristic of a certain
cognitive style, I call this "the implied critic's
decision style". Paraphrasing Booth (1961: 71-76)
on "the implied author", the implied critic
can be defined as the person whose decisions are reflected
in a given piece of criticism. "We infer him as
an ideal, literary, created version of the real man;
he is the sum of his choices" (74-75). Such differences
in decision style sometimes result in legitimate variant
readings; in some other instances, however, some readers
may display a tendency to avoid readings that exert
too much uncertainty or emotional ambivalence, and
prefer readings that appear less legitimate than the
avoided ones.
Poetry and Altered States of Consciousness
One of man's greatest achievements is personal consciousness. 6
At a very early age he learns to construct
stable categories that make a stable world from streams
of sensory information that flood his senses. We have
already encountered the relative advantages and disadvantages
of rapid and delayed categorisation. Stable, well-organised
categories constitute a relatively easily manipulable
small load of information on one's cognitive system;
on the other hand, they entail the loss of important
sensory information, that might be crucial for the
process of accurate adaptation. Exposure to fluid precategorial
information, by contrast, may load too much sensory
load on the human memory system; this overload may
be available for adaptive purposes and afford great
flexibility, but may be time-and-energy consuming,
and occupy too much mental processing space. Delayed
categorisation may involve a period of uncertainty
that may be quite unpleasant, or even intolerable for
some individuals. The solution to this catch appears
to be what Ehrenzweig (1970: 135) describes as "a
creative ego rhythm that swings between focussed Gestalt
and an oceanic undifferentiation".
The London psychoanalysts D.W. Winnicott and Marion Milner, have stressed the importance for a creative ego to be able to suspend the boundaries between self and not-self in order to become more at home in the world of reality where the objects and self are clearly held apart (ibid).Seen in this way, the oceanic experience of fusion, of a "return to the womb", represents the minimum content of all art; Freud saw in it only the basic religious experience. But it seems now that it belongs to all creativity (ibid).
In some people's responses to Alterman's metaphor in
quote 3 one may detect precisely such an element of
the suspension of boundaries between self and not-self,
of immersion in a thing-free and gestalt-free quality.
Altered states of consciousness are states in which
one is exposed for extended periods of time to precategorial,
or low-categorised information of varying sorts. These
would include a wide range of states in which the actively
organising mind is not in full control, ranging from
hypnagogic states (when one is half-awake, half-asleep),
through hypnotic state, to varieties of religious experience,
most notably mystic and ecstatic experiences. In the
creative process, moments of "inspiration"
or of "insight" too may involve such altered
state of consciousness, though less readily recognised
as such.
Since much Romantic and Symbolist poetry on the one
hand and religious poetry of most styles on the other
seek to be exposed to rich precategorial information,
we might expect to find in these styles and genres
poems that seek to achieve, or to display as a regional
quality, some altered state of consciousness.
In what follows, I am going to discuss at some length Keats's sonnet "On Seeing the Elgin Marbles".7
(5) My spirit is too week -- mortality
Weighs heavily on me like unwilling sleep,
And each imagined pinnacle and steep
Of godlike hardship, tell me I must die
Like a sick Eagle looking at the sky.
Yet 'tis a gentle luxury to weep
That I have not the cloudy winds to keep
Fresh for the opening of the morning's eye.
Such dim-conceivèd glories of the brain
Bring round the heart an indescribable feud;
So do these wonders a most dizzy pain,
That mingles Grecian grandeur with the rude
Wasting of old Time -- with a billowy main --
A sun -- a shadow of a magnitude.
This sonnet is quite remarkable in the poetry of altered
states of consciousness. This is one of the exquisite
instances in which Keats achieves one of his "many
havens of intensity". This is a kind of "peak
experience", similar to ecstasy; and it is, definitely,
a prominent kind of "altered state of consciousness".
A unique feature of this poem is that it begins with
a direct reference to a rather common kind of altered
state of consciousness, "unwilling sleep",
whether unwilling to come or to go, usually called
"hypnagogic". In what follows I shall try
to trace, briefly, the cumulative impact of elements
that contribute to this effect of peak experience.
I would point out two aspects of this emotional state:
passive emotional receptivity, far away from the "actively
organising mind"; and a state describable as "awe":
an overwhelming feeling of reverence, admiration, fear,
produced by that which is grand, sublime, extremely
powerful, or the like. In Keats's sonnet, "My
spirit is too weak" is a straightforward enough
conceptual statement of an emotional state suggesting
a relaxation of volitional control; while the landscape
descriptions "each imagined pinnacle and steep
/ Of godlike hardship... / a billowy main / A sun
a shadow of a magnitude", as well as "wonders...
Grecian grandeur" can be characterised as "grand,
sublime, extremely powerful".
This sonnet contains a considerable number of abstractions
and thing-free qualities which are the source of
emotionally loaded, undifferentiated qualities.
Here, I want to point out that mortality in line 1
makes an impression that may be described as a diffuse
though intense essence or quality. The sonnet begins
in a way that could be perceived as almost plain conceptual
language. "My spirit is too weak" is, as
I said, a straightforward enough conceptual statement
of an emotional state suggesting a relaxation of volitional
control. "Weighs heavily on me" is, in ordinary
language, a dead metaphor, in the sense 'troubles
me'. Nevertheless, the first two lines are rather perceived
as undifferentiated and non-conceptual. Why? One
reason could be the peculiar tension between the abstract
and the concrete in the sentence "Mortality weighs
heavily on me like unwilling sleep". Another reason
may be the peculiar nature of the concrete element
in this tension. Finally, the perceived quality generated
in this way is reinforced by the relation of this phrase
to the surrounding phrases.
If one may speak of relatively more and less abstract
nouns, mortality is more abstract than death, in the
sense that the potential is more abstract than the
actual. Besides, we are accustomed to personifications
of Death in poetry, myth, and even our every-day
thought, to the extent that we no longer associate
such personifications with pure abstractions; by
contrast, mortality is shape-free in our awareness.
In this sense, mortality stretches the expression into
the abstract direction. Weighs, on the other hand,
attributes to mortality a property which is the exclusive
property of physical objects. Now, when an abstraction
is associated with a physical object that has a characteristic
visual shape, the typical result is a figurative expression
in which the abstraction has a compact, differentiated,
conceptual character. When, however, the abstraction
is associated with a physical quality that belongs
to the domain of one of the least differentiated senses,
such as the tactile or thermal sense, or the sense
of weight it tends to be registered as a diffuse, undifferentiated
though intense and saturated percept. By attributing
weight to mortality, one endows it with potency, or
power. In this way, the present metaphor joins
a highly abstract (differentiated) noun with a very
low-differentiated predicate; there is a "hole"
left at what Wimsatt (1954) calls the substantive level
(that is to say, the expression suggests the kind of
feeling for which our vocabulary has no name). In the
present case, inasmuch as the metaphor is immediately
preceded by a direct expression "My spirit is
too weak" on the substantive level, it serves
as a standard for deviation in either direction. Notice
that the analysis depends on a certain mental performance:
it takes for granted that the predicate weighs is not
taken in the straightforward idiomatic sense of "troubles
me". But the qualities that are suggested here
as inherent in the predicate can be detected only if
one understands weighs as a physical attribute proper,
and conceives of the term as allowing, at one and the
same time, for a more abstract and a more concrete
interpretation of the expression on the substantive
level than it, taken by itself, would suggest. Here,
such a reading is encouraged by the sequel, "like
unwilling sleep" (meaning either unwilling to
come or to vanish), which metonymically transfers
an undifferentiated sense of heaviness from the limbs
to mortality, the abstraction being related to
the speaker from the outside, as it were.
In the following, I shall propose a few comments on
the poem's ensuing landscape description. According
to our foregoing assumption concerning the relationship
between landscape descriptions and emotional qualities
in poetry, one might expect that the "pinnacles
and steeps" amplify the emotional quality of mortality,
by increasing its diffuseness. This, however, is not
necessarily the case. Alternative mental performances
may be involved, and the reader may switch back and
forth between them. Horizontally, "Each imagined
pinnacle and steep" may be conceived of as of
part of an actual, continuous landscape; vertically,
as of strikingly representative examples of "godlike
hardship", that is, of a circumstance in which
excessive and painful effort of some kind is required.
Qua exemplary, the landscape tends to bring the conceptual
nature of hardship into sharp focus. Now, the more emphasis is placed on the
actual (rather than the exemplary) nature of the landscape,
the softer (the more diffuse) becomes the soft focus
of perception of the abstraction hardship. Alternatively,
the more our awareness is focused on the shapes of
the "pinnacles and steeps", the sharper the
definition gets of the conceptual quality; and, conversely,
the more one's awareness is focussed on locating oneself
in space and time with reference to the pinnacles and
steeps, the more diffuse (the more 'perceptual') the
concept becomes. All this is implied by our foregoing
discussion of orientation.
The line "Like a sick eagle looking at the sky"
has a multiple relationship to the preceding utterance.
First, the eagle reinforces connotations of loftiness
in "pinnacles and steeps". Second, the eagle
enacts the sense of desperate helplessness; it combines
in one visual image impending death with what the eagle
might be in the sky, and thus reinforces a tragic feeling.
Third, the mere appearance of the eagle enhances the
suggestion that the "pinnacles and steeps"
may constitute an actual landscape. Fourth, the eagle
"looking at the sky" represents a consciousness
in the very act of locating itself with reference to
space, that is, it emphasizes the aspect of spatial
orientation, rather than the exemplary aspect in "each
pinnacle and steep", and thus increases the diffuse,
rather than the compact perception of mortality and
also, possibly, of hardship.
Our discussion of the two aspects of "each imagined
pinnacle and steep" upon which awareness may be
focused, raises an additional issue of the utmost importance.
The theoretical equipment introduced here can help
to discern some crucial respects in which allegory
is distinguished from symbol. Traditionally, both suggest
a kind of 'double-talk': talking of some concrete entities
and implying some abstract ones. But whereas in allegory
the concrete or material forms are considered as the
"mere" guise of some well-defined abstract
or spiritual meaning, the symbol is conceived to have
an existence independent from the abstractions, and
to suggest, "somehow", the ineffable,
some reality, or quality, or feeling, that cannot be
expressed in ordinary, conceptual language. The
landscape in Keats's sonnet can be perceived as an
allegorical landscape, strikingly representative of
"godlike hardship", or as a symbolic landscape,
suggesting certain feelings that tend to elude words.
Now, ineffable experiences are ineffable precisely
because they are related to right-hemisphere brain
activities, in which information is diffuse, undifferentiated,
global, whereas the language which seeks to express
those experiences is a typical left-hemisphere brain-activity,
in which information is compact, well-differentiated,
and linear. Traditional allegory bestows well-differentiated
physical shapes and human actions upon clear-cut ideas,
which can be represented in clear, conceptual language
as well; by contrast, the symbol manipulates information
in such a way that some (or most) of it is perceived
as diffuse, undifferentiated, global. The symbol does
this by associating information with the cognitive
mechanism of spatial orientation, or by treating it
in terms of the least differentiated senses, or by
presenting its elements in multiple relationships
(cf. Tsur, 1987a: 1-4); all these techniques can be
reinforced by what I have called "divergent structures".
One might further highlight the peculiar semantic nature of the present sonnet by comparing its lines 9-10 to three lines from Marlowe's tragedy "Tamburlaine".
(6) Such dim-conceivèd glories of the brain
Bring round the heart an indescribable feud ...(7) Nature that framed us of four elements,
Warring within our breasts for regiment,
Doth teach us all to have aspiring minds.
In spite of Tamburlaine's and Faustus' notorious
craving for infinite things in Marlowe's tragedies,
we may expect, from a common, sweeping generalization,
Keats's poetry to be of a more romantic, more affective
mood than Marlowe's poetry. It would be interesting
to see whether and how the two passages bear out such
pieces of "common knowledge".
The two passages have a considerable number of elements in common. Both refer, in a fairly direct way, to an undifferentiable feeling, in terms of a "gestalt-free" quality, by linguistic terms that are near-synonyms: a war "within our breasts", and a feud "round the heart", and its relation to what happens in our minds (or in the brain). For Keats, as a true Romantic, this is an intense passion at unique moments. It is set in a specific setting which also indicates the immediate cause of the intense passion: "On Seeing the Elgin Marbles". This passion is so intense that it cannot be sustained for a considerable period. For Marlowe, this feeling is rather a permanent disposition. Some readers report that they perceive a heightened affective quality in (6), as compared to (7). One possible explanation for this may rely on the different connotations of warring and feud. But far more significant seems to be the fact that whereas in Marlowe's passage it is the clearly differentiated "four elements" that are "warring within our breasts", Keats's "feud" around the heart is not only undifferentiated and gestalt-free, but thing-free too: in ordinary referential language we expect to be told the feud is taking place between whom or what. Moreover, the location "round the heart" is clearly included in "within our breasts"; but as for their psychological atmosphere, the former phrase is perceived as vague, indistinct, whereas the latter as contained within clear boundaries. Thus, the more passionate impact of Keats's lines has to do with the fact that they are focused on violent actions, stripped of things that might carry them. Furthermore, although both metaphors seem to refer to some kind of emotional turbulence, Marlowe uses rhetorical devices to heighten its conscious "linear" quality, whereas Keats uses devices to mute, or obscure, this conscious quality. Marlowe's "warring within our breasts" is endowed with the psychological atmosphere of patent purpose, generated by the purposive ingredient in the words and phrases "for regiment", "teach", "aspiring minds", as well as by the conclusive nature of all. One interesting contrast between the two passages concerns the explicit use of the personal pronoun "our" by Marlowe, and the conspicuously impersonal constructs in Keats's two verses, de-emphasising the involvement of a purposeful agent (I shall return to this point).
Keats, on the other hand, emphasizes the undifferentiated
character of the passion by the adjectives "indescribable
feud", and "dim-conceivèd glories".
I shall refrain from discussing all the aspects relevant
to this comparison. I only want to discuss here the
phrase "glories of the brain". Consider such
sentences as "the brain has glories" and
"the brain is glorious". In these two phrases,
brain is the referring expression, and glories or glorious
denote a property attributed to the brain. The phrase
"glories of the brain" can be thought of
in a somewhat antiquated framework, as derived from
the other two phrases through two transformations:
the nominalization of the "deep" predicate,
and its permutation into the referring position in
the surface phrase. We may call such genitive phrases
"nominalized predicates". They shift
the focus of attention from "things as bundles
of properties" to their "sensed properties",
dissociated to some degree from the things. In the
present context, this can be regarded as a kind of
regression to a "pre-thing" state, reinforcing
the thing-free quality encountered in feud.
This comparison of the two passages does not greatly
differ from the usual techniques of close reading.
Nonetheless, our discussion of consciousness and of
the categorization of information conveys several
significant contributions. Theories of metaphor
explore, typically, such issues as how to furnish the
best possible paraphrase for a metaphor, or how
people understand novel metaphors. Here we have
two metaphors that do not differ significantly
in their meanings, but rather in their perceived
effects. The cognitive frame of reference has contributed
to an explanation of this difference: It has explained
the relationship between certain linguistic structures
and the "regression" to a low-category mode
of perception; it has also explained, in turn, the
relationship of such regression to the affective quality
of the text, as well as to our cognitive characterization
of poetry. We have also indicated how these relationships
can be further pursued, so as to relate the texts to
the effects of period and style, such as Classic/Romantic.
In the present context, it also suggests how this difference
may contribute to a distinction between some permanent
mood and an altered state of consciousness. One may,
further, claim that it was the cognitive framework
that suggested these linguistic tools for description;
in a different frame of reference these descriptions
would have appeared little more than trivial.
Presenting semantic elements in multiple relationships
is the favorite object of New Criticism's ambiguity-hunting.
Consider, for instance, "Such dim-conceivèd
glories of the brain". "Glory" is a
fairly clear-cut notion, denoting, for our purpose,
'exalted or adoring praise', or 'an object of pride',
or 'splendour, brilliance, halo'. "Glories of
the brain" may mean, accordingly, either 'adoring
glories given to the object of Greek Art' (the glories
of the onlooker's brain); or '"The Elgin Marbles"
are objects of pride, the glories of the creator's
brain'. "Dim" as a muting adjective brings
out the brilliance aspect of "glory". Thus,
again we have a sensuous presentation of the irrational
response: sight is the most differentiated of the senses,
hence serving conventionally as metaphor for rational
faculties. Though "dim" turns "glories",
implicitly, into light, it is "dim" that
makes the light less distinct, less differentiable.
Similarly, the "dim-conceivèd glories"
of the creator's brain stem from the dark layers of
the unconscious mind. Now consider "dim-conceivèd".
Which one of its possible meanings would be relevant
to the poem? "To conceive of" means 'To comprehend
through the intellect something not perceived through
the senses'. "To conceive" means 'to relate
ideas or feelings to one another in a pattern'; or,
in a different sense, 'to become pregnant' yielding
a fairly physical metaphor for irrational bringing
forth. At any rate, "dim" and "glories"
foreshadow, as it were, the more objectively presented
"sun" and "shadow" in the last
line. Thus, to put it in Arthur Mizener's terms (1964:
142) echoing Bergson on "metaphysical intuition",
no single meaning of these words will these lines work
out completely, nor will the language allow any one
of the several emergent figures to usurp our attention.
Thus, the blurred meanings contribute to the diffuse
perception of the sonnet. In cognitive terms we might
speak of overloading the cognitive system with these
rival meanings. In terms of figure-ground relationship
we might say that we handle the potentially well-defined
meanings by "dumping" them in an undifferentiated
"ground". The process is not unlike
that in the visual mode, where well-defined shapes,
when endlessly repeated or superimposed one upon the other,
are perceived as undifferentiated ground.
The adjective in "Of godlike hardship" means 'like, or befitting a god'; and it may suggest either 'hardship that only a god can endure', or 'hardship that only a god can inflict'. In this way, the word godlike fuses two plains of reality: that of the experiencing subject, and of the external object. There is a similar ambiguity in wonders in line 11, meaning either 'something that causes astonishment, admiration, or awe', or 'the emotion excited by what is strange, admirable or surprising'. In such ambiguities (of which there are quite a few in this sonnet) the various meanings tend to blur each other, preventing each other from usurping the entire available mental space. In my discussion of "each imagined pinnacle and steep" I suggested two alternative mental performances, a vertical and a horizontal one: the former suggesting strikingly representative examples of "godlike hardship", the latter suggesting an actual, continuous landscape; in the present context one might suggest a third kind of mental performance, in which the various meanings are simultaneously active, blurring each other and preventing each other from usurping the whole available mental space. That is how a soft, integrated focus of meanings is achieved in this poem, underlying its intense emotional quality. In order to appreciate how this process works, compare, for instance, the following two passages:
(8) And each imagined pinnacle and steep
Of godlike hardship, tell me I must die
and
(9) At the round earth's imagined corners blow
Your trumpets, Angels ...
In the latter quotation, the referents of two incompatible
geometrical terms (round and corners) are superimposed
upon one another, generating a sharp conflict. The
term imagined is meant here to mitigate the conflict,
but, by the same token, it creates another impossiblity:
The angels are really standing at the imagined corners.
Thus, rather than blurring one another, the conflicting
elements strive to establish themselves in the reader's
perception, creating a split, sharp focus, generating
a witty quality.
I have described the synchronic effect of images hovering between a subjective and an objective existence. They have, however, a diachronic aspect too. The octet is dominated by first person singular pronouns; they disappear in the sestet all in all. Most conspicuous are the impersonal constructs "glories of the brain" and "round the heart", in stead of "glories of my brain", and "round my heart". Pain (in line 11) too is a psychological abstraction which, again, seems to be unrelated to any individual conciousness. The above ambiguous phrases serve as transition from the "I", the enduring, conscious element that knows experience to a less conscious state; that is, they serve as transition from a state of individual consciousness to an altered state of consciousness. In this state there is an awareness of a stream of images, but no awareness of the self as thinking, feeling, and willing, and distinguishing itself from selves of others and from objects of its thought. It concerns an "ability to make up one's mind about nothingto let the mind be a thoroughfare for all thoughts" (Keats, 1956: 26). This stream of images, dissociated from the self as thinking, feeling, and willing, and distinguishing itself from selves of others and from objects of its thought, leads to a state of consciousness designated as "a most dizzy pain". "Pain" merely names an acute but undifferentiated feeling. While not diminishing the intensity of pain, "dizzy" blurs its contours. "Dizzy" refers to a whirling state of uneasy feeling, sometimes extremely intense, blurring one's perception of the external world. The last tercet gives us the "chemical makup" of this "dizzy pain": it "mingles Grecian grandeur with the rude wasting of old Time--with a billowy main--a sun--a shadow of a magnitude". In an attempt to understand the poetic significance of such a structure, let us quote Bergson on "metaphysical intuition", as quoted by Ehrenzweig who regards it as a gestalt-free vision:
"When I direct my attention inward to contemplate my own self [...] I perceive at first, as a crust solidified at the surface, all the perceptions which come to it from the material world. These perceptions are clear, distinct, juxtaposed or juxtaposable one with another; they tend to group themselves into objects. [...] But if I draw myself in from the periphery towards the centre [...] I find an altogether different thing. There is beneath these sharply cut crystals and this frozen surface a continuous flux which is not comparable to any flux I have ever seen. There is a succession of states each of which announces that which follows and contains that which precedes it. In reality no one begins or ends, but all extend into each other" (Ehrenzweig, l965: 34-35).
In Keats's sonnet, the constitutents of the "dizzy
pain" are expressed by syntactically juxtaposed
phrases; but the referents of those phrases are said
to be "mingled". What is more, with the exception
of "A sun", they don't "group themselves
into objects", into "sharply cut crystals
and [...] frozen surface"; all the rest are thing-free
and gestalt-free entities, which have no clear-cut
solid boundaries, so that they don't resist entering
the "succession of states" in which "no
one begins or ends, but all extend into each other".
The notorious 18th-century diction embodied in "billowy
main" has in this context a special effect. This
kind of diction makes use, as Wimsatt pointed out,
of a general term as "main" (in the sense
of 'broad expanse') with an epithet denoting one of
its concrete attributes, "billowy", skipping
the straightforward term on the "substantive level",
"ocean" or "high sea", generating
tension between the more than usually abstract and
the more than usually concrete. Both terms of the phrase
designate gestalt-free entities, and in the present
context suggest enormous energy.
Grandeur and magnitude are etymologically synonymous.
Nonetheless, they have acquired different senses: the
former applies to the impressive, the latter to the
measurable qualities of things (in this sense, too,
the sonnet moves from the subjective towards the more
objective). Their sublime effect is cumulative. The
sun and the shadow are clear opposites fit for a forceful
ending of a sonnet dominated by indistinct--though sublime--passions.
Nonetheless, "a shadow of a magnitude" intimates
some essence beyond the perceptible realm. Both shadow
and magnitude are attributes of physical objects. The
shadow is but a reflection of an object; magnitude
is an abstraction from an object; the "object"
itself, which remains unnamed, has been skipped--generating
high metaphoric tension between both sides of the omitted
"substantive level". The magnitude is here
a thing-free abstraction--casting a visible shadow; and
here we have the sun that gives the light--to make the
shadow-casting more real. Does this not suggest, even
make us visualise, so to speak, a most intense, supersensuous
reality beyond the "cave" we are bound to
live in?
Thus, Keats's sonnet begins with a rather trivial kind of altered state of consiousness, suggested by the low-differentiated predicate "weighs" applied to the abstract subject "mortality" on the one hand, and the hypnagogic state "unwilling sleep" on the other hand. It moves through successions of sublime entities beginning with a concrete landscape and culminating in a most intense low-differentiated, diffuse "peak experience" affording an insight into an iperceptible world "beyond". The peculiar rhyme-structure of the sestet in this sonnet makes a unique contribution to this diffuse "open" ending. The so-called Italian Sonnet may have a variety of rhyme-patterns in its sestet; in this sonnet the rhyme pattern is: ababab. Suppose the sonnet ended with an abab quatrain, say
(10) Such dim-conceivèd glories of the brain
Bring round the heart an indescribable feud;
So do these wonders a most dizzy pain,
A sun -- a shadow of a magnitude.
Irrespective of the illogical linking of the last line
to the preceding ones, such a structure generates a
symmetrical, stable ending. The fourth line of the
unit constitutes a highly required closure. Now when
you have not four but six lines, in an ababab pattern,
in stead of a stable closure, you obtain a fluid pattern.
The fluidity of this pattern is further heightened
by the tense enjambment "with the rude / Wasting
of old Time". If the closed ending of (10) has
a highly-differentiated symmetrical shape, inducing
a rational perceptual quality, the open ending of (5)
has a fluid, low-differentiated, diffuse quality, reinforcing
the low-differentiated, diffuse state of consciousness
indicated at the semantic and thematic level of the
sonnet.
Now consider this. The present sonnet is exceptional in an important sense even among Keats's "ecstatic" poems. In the best of romantic ecstatic poetry, we find sometimes that inactivity through death is counterbalanced by some intense activity, or immense sublimity (connoting intensity). Thus we find that in some of Keats's poems ecstasy is achieved by using death-imagery in a context of intense passion. Consider the endings of some of the sonnets in which Keats achieves his "many havens of intensity".
(11) ...then on the shore
Of the wide world I stand alone and think
Till Love and Fame to nothingness do sink.
(Keats, "When I have fears")(12) Still, still to hear her tender-taken breath,
And so live ever--or else swoon to death.
(Keats, "Bright Star")(13) Love, Fame and Beauty are intense indeed,
But death intenser; Death is Life's high meed.
(Keats, "Why did I laugh?")
According to Barbara Herrnstein-Smith, the mention of
death or nothingness at the end of such a poem constitutes
a "closural allusion", arousing a vague feeling
that there is nothing after this. The couplet following
the quatrains reinforces this feeling of closure. Thus,
in these sonnets, the mention of death (coupled with
intense passion) generates a feeling of ecstasy, or
"peak experience"; this feeling of "peak"
is reinforced by the structural closure of the couplet,
generating a conclusive tone. In Keats's Elgin-Marbles
sonnet, by contrast, there is no such mention of death,
or structural closure. On the contrary rather, the
ababab rhyme-pattern commits a "sabotage"
against the symmetrical abab grouping, while the run-on
line toward the end commits another "sabotage",
against the two-line groupings of ab. In this way,
in spite of the rigorous rhyme pattern, there is here
a feeling of dissolving shapes reinforcing any impression
of dissolving consciousness suggested by the contents
and the semantic structure. The possible Platonic allusion
in "a shadow of a magnitude" suggests the
possibility of having caught a glimpse into some world
inaccessible to the senses.
Now a final comment on this sonnet and other similar ones. According to the conception propounded here, it does not arouse an ecstatic experience in the reader; it displays a regional quality which the reader recognises as ecstatic. We have followed at some length the verbal means which contribute to the perception of such an ecstatic regional quality.
This paper expounded some aspects of Cognitive Poetics. Its main object was to present some ways in which cognitive theories can be used systematically to relate the perceived affects of poetry to poetic structures. It explored some poetic techniques by which nonconceptual experiences can be conveyed, or displayed, by the use of language which is conceptual in nature. By the same token, it briefly considered the influence of personality style on the reader's or the critic's abiliy to respond to the poetic qualities.
1. This paper was intended to be one of two introductory chapters to a collection of essays by members of the Cognitive Poetics Workshop run for over 15 years at the Katz Research Institute, Tel Aviv University, directed by David Gil, Yeshayahu Shen and myself (in an alphabethical order). Eventually we had to abandon the publication project, because we could not raise the necessary funds. I have omitted the section on metre (see now my "book in progress").
2. I am indebted to Professor Pinchas Noy for the Helen Keller story.Conscious logic is out of action, its rules have lost their forces. One of the mechanisms now in action can cause, in a dream, two words to become one, or merge two figures in one. This peculiarity of the psychic apparatus is sometimes exploited in jokes. If, for instance, we describe the Christmas vacations as "Alcoholidays", we understand that the new word, the pun word, is obviously composed of two parts: of "alcohol" and "holidays": they are united or--as we say--"condensed". An analogous condensation could also have arisen in a dream. But unlike the dream, the pun is thought out, created. We make use intentionally--which is not synonymous with consciously--of a primitive mechanism in order to achieve a particular aim".In fact--as Freud has shown us--in all play with words, in puns as well as nonsense talk, there is a renewal of the child's pleasure when it just learns to master language. [...] At bottom caricature, too, renews infantile pleasure. Its simplicity [...] makes it resemble the scribbling of the child. [...] Caricatures like those of Louis Philippe as a pear are at bottom nothing but visual puns, and the taste in puns may change but their mechanism remains the same (Kris and Gombrich, 1965: 196-197).
4. Such a prolongation may cause a feeling of unease that may be intolerable for some readers. Not all people are equally capable of enduring the contact with uncategorized or meaningless objects or stimuli; this depends, to a considerable extent, on personality style. "The leveler is more anxious to categorize sensations and less willing to give up a category once he has established it. [...] For him the unique, unclassifiable sensation is particularly offensive" (Ohmann, 1970: 231; cf. Tsur, 1975a; 1987a: 1-59; 1992: 367-373, 471-500).
5. This usage of sensuous metaphors is highly sophisticated and rather exceptional. Gardner, Winner and their associates have produced ample evidence that preschool children are highly creative in producing metaphors; but all the metaphors they create are sensuous. Only at later stages of their development do children produce functional metaphors, or metaphors whose tenor is conceptual or pertaining to psychological dispositions. As understanders, young children tend to prefer sensuous metaphors, whose grounds are similar shapes or, later, similar colors. Only at later stages, after a so-called "literal period", they develop a taste for the other kinds of metaphors (cf. Gardner, 1982: 158-167; Gardner & Winner, 1979: 125-134; Silberstein et al., 1982). In the years preceding adolescence, when children have begun to allow a metaphoric renaming, their practice is characterized by "a greater awareness that tension has been overridden" (Gardner and Winner, 1979: 134); not so the preschool child whose practice is characterized by a "more carefree experimentation" (ibid.).
I have elsewhere (Tsur, 1987c: 154-158; 1992: 370) attempted
to show that Mediaeval Hebrew poets, especially in
the genre of garden-descriptions, indulged in sensuous
metaphors in a manner that is closer to a "more
carefree experimentation" than to the arousal
of surprise or to the creation of perplexity, startling,
astounding. To be sure, in this manner, too, they often
achieved enormous complexity, but still in a relatively
"more carefree experimentation". It is interesting
to note that critics are reluctant to acknowledge sensuous
metaphors in either the carefree, or the disorienting
version, and that they presumably do this for different,
or even opposite, reasons: while the disorienting use
of sensuous metaphors may be painful to face, effects
of the "carefree" use of sensuous metaphors
may be experienced as too naive, or even too childish,
for their sophisticated taste. I am still collecting
information in order to work out this distinction between
the two uses of sensuous metaphors in greater detail.
6. I have elsewhere discussed poetry and altered states of consciousness at very great length (Tsur, 1992: 411-470).
7. I have discussed rhythmic problems of this poem and some solutions offered to them in Douglas Hodge's performance in Tsur (in press).
Beardsley, Monroe C. (1958) Aesthetics: Problems in
the Philosophy of Criticism. New York & Burlingame:
Harcourt, Brace & World.
Bierwisch, Manfred (1970) "Poetics and Linguistics",
in Donald C. Freeman (ed.), Linguistics and Literary
Style. New York: Holt, Rinehart & Winston. 97-115.
Booth, Wayne C. (1961) The Rhetoric of Fiction. Chicago:
Chicago UP.
Brooke-Rose, Christine (1958) A Grammar of Metaphor.
London: Secker & Warburg.
Burke, Kenneth (l957) The Philosophy of Literary Form,
New York: Vintage.
Culler, Jonathan (1975) Structuralist Poetics. London:
Routledge & Kegan Paul.
D'Andrade, Roy Godwin (1980) "The Cultural Part
of Cognition", Address Given to the 2nd Annual
Cognitive Science Conference, New Haven.
Ehrenzweig, Anton (1965) The Psychoanalysis of Artistic
Vision and Hearing. New York: Braziller.
Ehrenzweig, Anton (1970) The Hidden Order of Art. London:
Paladin.
Gardner, Howard (1982) Art, Mind, & Brain. New York:
Basic Books.
Gardner, Howard and Ellen Winner (1979) "The Development
of Metaphoric Competence: Implications for Humanistic
Disciplines", in Sheldon Sachs (ed.), On Metaphor.
Chicago: Chicago UP. 121-139.
Herrnstein-Smith, Barbara (1968) Poetic Closure. Chicago:
Chicago UP.
Jakobson, Roman (1960) "Closing Statement: Linguistics
and Poetics", in Thomas A. Sebeok (ed.), Style
in Language. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT. 350-377.
Keats, John (1956) The Selected Letters of John Keats,
Lionel Trilling (ed.). Garden City, N.Y.: Doubleday
Anchor.
Kris, Ernst (1965) Psychoanalytic Explorations in Art.
New York: Schocken.
Kris, Ernst, and E. H. Gombrich (1965) "The Principles
of Caricature", in Ernst Kris, Psychoanalytic
Explorations in Art. New York: Schocken.
Mizener, Arthur (1964) "The Structure of Figurative
Language in Shakespeare's Sonnets", in Barbara
Herrnstein ed., Discussions of Shakespeare's Sonnets.
Boston: D. C. Heath and Company. 137-151.
Ohmann, Richard (1970b) "Modes of Order",
in Freeman, Donald C. (ed.), Linguistics and Literary
Style. New York: Holt, Rinehart & Winston. 209-242.
Ornstein, Robert E. (1975) The Psychology of Consciousness.
Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Preminger, Alex & T. V. F. Brogan (1993) The New
Princeton Encyclopedia of Poetry and Poetics. Princeton:
Princeton UP.
Plutchik, R. (1968 [19621] "The Evolutionary Basis
of Emotional Behaviour", in Magda B. Arnold (ed.),
The Nature of Emotion. Harmondsworth: Penguin. 67-80.
Posner, Michael I. (1973) Cognition: An Introduction.
Glenview Il. & Brighton, England: Scott, Foreman
& Co.
Silberstein, Lisa, Howard Gardner, Erin Phelps &
Ellen Winner (1982) "Autumn Leaves and Old Photographs:
The Developments of Metaphor Preferences". Journal
of Experimental Child Psychology 34: 135-150.
Thomson, Philip (1972) The Grotesque. London: Methuen.
Tsur, Reuven (1975a) "Two Critical Attitudes: Quest
for Certitude and Negative Capability". College
English 36: 776-778.
Tsur, Reuven (1978) "Emotions, Emotional Qualities
and Poetry" (in English). Psychocultural Review
2: 165-180.
Tsur, Reuven (1987a). The Road to "Kubla Khan".
Jerusalem: Israel Science Publishers.
Tsur, Reuven (1987b). On Metaphoring. Jerusalem: Israel
Science Publishers.
Tsur, Reuven (1987c) Mediaeval Hebrew Poetry in a Double
PerspectiveThe Versatile Reader and Hebrew Poetry in
Spain. Tel Aviv: University Publishing Projects (In
Hebrew).
Tsur, Reuven (1988a). Hebrew Hypnotic Poetry. Tel Aviv:
The Katz Research Institute for Hebrew Literature (in
Hebrew).
Tsur, Reuven (1988b) "'Oceanic' Dedifferentiation
and Poetic Metaphor". Journal of Pragmatics 12:
711-724.
Tsur, Reuven (1992) Toward a Theory of Cognitive Poetics.
Amsterdam: Elsevier (North Holland) Science Publishers.
Tsur, R., Glicksohn, J., & Goodblatt, C. (1990)
"Perceptual Organization, Absorption and Aesthetic
Qualities of Poetry". László Halász
(ed.), Proceedings of the 11th International Congress
on Empirical Aesthetics. Budapest: Institute for Psychology
of the Hungarian Academy of Sciences. 301-304.
Tsur, R., Glicksohn, J., & Goodblatt, C. (1991)
"Gestalt Qualities in Poetry and the Reader's
Absorption Style". Journal of Pragmatics 16 (5):
487-504.
Wellek, René & Austin Warren (1956) Theory
of Literature. New York: Harcourt, Brace & Co.
Wimsatt, W. K. (1954) The Verbal Icon. New York: Noonday.
This page was created using TextToHTML. TextToHTML is a free software for Macintosh and is (c) 1995,1996 by Kris Coppieters